Bondarev-Philosophy_Freedom_Vol_2_Ch6
G. A. Bondarev

Rudolf Steiners "Philosophy of Freedom" as the Foundation of Logic of Beholding Thinking, Religion of the Thinking Will, Organon of the New Cultural Epoch
Volume 2


Part VI. The Concept (the Idea) and the Percept (Experience)


1. The Three Worlds
2. The Genesis of the Concept
3. 'Sensory Appearance' and 'Thinking' in the World-View of Ideal-Realism
4. Goethe, Hegel and Rudolf Steiner
5. The Natural-Scientific Method of Goethe and Rudolf Steiner
6. The Subject of Cognition

Chapter 4 – The World as Percept



1. The Three Worlds

The experience of knowledge which we have acquired as a result of our work with the first three chapters of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’, allows us to make certain generalizations. The conscious being of man stands before us as an activity that is carried out at the meeting-point of three worlds, each one of which has its representation within the cognizing ‘I’. Thanks to this fact the latter has in the human being the character of a self-conscious principle.

The first of these three worlds is the sense-world, given to us in (outer and inner) percepts. The second world is thinking. In its essential nature it stands beyond subject and object. The phenomenon of thinking in man is merely a special case – albeit one of immense significance – within the total structure of the universal being of thinking. This world will, more than once, be an object of our discussions, but for the present we will “make do” with a general characterization. The universal world of thinking is the primal source and the ideal foundation of all being. In its manifestation before created things it was (and remains) the world of (in the view of Scholasticism) the essential intelligible beings, the thought-beings. Concepts and ideas serve as the representatives of this world in human consciousness.

With the accumulation of (pure and empirical) knowledge there emerges in the human being a soul world of his own which sends its representatives in the form of memories into the active life of the human spirit. This world stands as a subjective one over against the objectivity of the first two worlds. For the becoming of the human ‘I’, all three worlds are equally indispensable. If any one of them is excluded, the human individuality simply does not come into being. The consequences arising from this are many and various. Firstly it gives us full justification in asking: If the existence of the human individuality has an objective character, is it possible to exclude it and to regard the first two worlds as fully existent nevertheless? If not – and this is the second point – can one then regard the phenomenology of the human spirit as being without foundation? Do we have the right to dispute the fact that the conceptual expression of the world-intelligence in man is an objective process which constitutes a part of the world process as a whole?

The answer to these questions can provide the solution to the riddle of the human being, and it can be found through spiritual-scientific study of the genesis of world and man.

In the sphere of soul-spiritual processes, the ontogenesis, within the subject, of its ‘I’-consciousness, is of decisive significance. As we have already described, this ‘I’-consciousness is supported upon the reality of the three worlds, where the percept plays the role of “prime mover”. It calls forth of necessity in the subject – so we read in the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ – the manifestation of the corresponding concept, which arises from the world of thinking. Their union gives rise to the inner representations as the content of the individual spirit (mind). They accumulate within it and, through the cognitive activity of the ‘I’, are brought together into the system of a world-view (Welt-anschauung) – thus providing the basis for the motives of activity.

All this can be shown in its entirety in diagrammatic form (Fig.56). As all that is real in the world is personified, we must imagine behind the three worlds which are the object of our study, the presence of creative ‘I’- beings through whom their selfhood and their self-development are conditioned. Behind the world given to us in percepts (the sense-world) there stands the ‘I’ of the universe. But this also stands behind the world of thinking, which is none other than the universal individual (see Figs. 17 and 25a). In relation to the cognizing subject the ‘I’ of the universe appears in two aspects: outwardly (‘I’-1.) through perception, and inwardly (‘I’- 2.) through thinking. The ‘I’ at the apex of the triangle and the ‘I’ at its centre are one and the same – i.e. the lower ‘I’ of the individual, which is in a process of development. But there are also differences between them. The ‘I’ in the centre is the one that is decidedly the lower; the ‘I’ at the apex is in touch with the higher ‘I’, which is becoming individualized in the human being and which exists (and is active) potentially behind the spiritual world of the human being and makes its presence felt in him from time to time; thanks to it, or within it, there also takes place the process of the “gathering in” of the personality, its involution.

In the early stages of the objective evolution of the human monad, its involution had an entirely substantial character: As the Hierarchies thought the human being, they created his triune corporeality. In the first stages of the development of ‘I’-consciousness the thought-pictures experienced by the human being also influenced his corporeality fundamentally, but especially the substances of his soul-body and his sentient soul. All this had a decisive influence on the character of the different religious beliefs and rituals and the modes of upbringing and education. Depending upon which Gods men worshipped, different types of personality developed among them; this even found expression in their outer appearance: there was the Apollonian and the Dionysian. One may confidently assert that also the racial differences between human beings are determined by their traditional, age-old forms of religious belief.


Something else emerges in the human being in the process of his individual evolution. The situation here is that, once we have become ‘I’-beings, we experience how the percepts give us the stimulus to the forming of concepts, but as yet we are not able to create conceptually, out of the ‘I’, a sense-perceptible object. Where our inner world is concerned, however, the complete reverse is true: the objects of perception within it (memories) can only be brought forth

through the conceptual, thinking activity of the ‘I’. We can only estimate the significance of this fact rightly, if we understand the human being as the unity of ‘I’ and the world. This is constituted through the totality of the three tri-unities, and consisting of 3 x 3 elements, which draws together the dynamic of the ‘I’-consciousness into a single whole, a system, the dynamic of the ascent from the lower ‘I’ to the higher ‘I’ (Fig.56a). Thus the human individual incorporates himself into the world-individual, grows into it, enriches it with the qualities of self-conditioned self-development under the conditions of free choice between being and not-being, between good and evil.

Within each of the tri-unities represented in the Figure, the elements of which they are composed can be regarded as identical in nature. In the process of the involution of the human spirit they form a hierarchy. It passes through this hierarchy in the process of its individual evolution which leads it via identification with its elements. In this case, progress is determined through the striving of the lower ‘I’, which is able to condition itself as it grows upwards into the higher ‘I’; then the concepts become identical with the percepts and memories. Potentially, within the system of tenfold man, all three ‘I’s of the inner triangle are identical.

In his characterization of Saint-Martin’s ten-leafed book Rudolf Steiner says that the main page in it is the tenth; without this, “all the preceding ones would be unknown.... the Primal Creator of things (but this is what man, too, must become – G.A.B.) (is) invincible by virtue of this tenth page, because it is a corral (a circle of wagons – Trans.) around him, through which no being can pass” (Beiträge 32. p.13). The tenth page forms the corral – to speak in the language of methodology – simply through transforming the structure of 3 x 3 elements into a unity, a system, thus leading them back to that from which they sprang – the original unity, the Creator.

In the case we are considering, the “corral” of the system of nine elements has taken on the character of a “fortress” consisting of three sets of walls. Behind these walls the true ‘I’ of the human being matures in its sovereign independence, whereby it bears the character of an active centre of transformation. Its “security” is not assured through isolation from the world, but through a lawfully structured dynamic connection and interaction with it. This is something like a state of “active defence” – a victorious resistance struggle of selfhood and of the maturing of the lower ‘I’ to the higher ‘I’ within the organic totality of the three worlds. Here the outer antithesis to God (in concept and percept) is transformed into the supremacy of God in the holy of holies of the individual ‘I’. Thus is realized the word of St. Paul “Not I, but Christ in me” – the higher principle of human freedom. Its stages are as follows: First the ‘I’ in its separation from the Divine world, then the sacrifice of the (lower) ‘I’ in Christ and, finally, resurrection in the higher ‘I’.


2. The Genesis of the Concept

In the considerations that are summed up in Fig.5, we showed, from the cultural-historical aspect, the general principle of the acquisition of the concept by the human being. We will now go on to examine the nature and significance of concepts, and their place within the structure of the unitary soul-spiritual entity man-world.

Rudolf Steiner describes the genesis of the concept in close connection with the process of man’s development in the course of the culture-epochs. All that occurred before them belongs to the cosmic “biography” of the concept, which could tell of the stages in world-development where the human being was no more than an object among many others.

In the first culture-epoch of our root-race, knowledge still flowed into the human being, as it were, directly from the spiritual world of imaginations. The purpose of the word was to evoke within the soul living pictures of what was knowable, and convey them to another soul. At that time no logic was possible. In the Old Persian epoch human beings also received concepts by way of supersensible mediation, but experiences of the sense-world began to determine their form. The Egyptians were the first to begin to apply concepts to the needs of the physical plane – in astrology, in surveying, in building. Concepts were given the form of symbols, but their supersensible substance withdrew from the human being. The fullness of the supersensible was experienced by the Egyptian in the form of a triangle, and he therefore experienced himself, – as a creature, a vessel of God – also as a tri-unity (see GA 124, 7.10.1911). In the Ancient Greek epoch man grew conscious of the fact that, when he gains knowledge of the world, he adds something new to it, and that in his thinking he is disconnected from the world. This began with Aristotle. Later, in the Middle Ages, the need arises to apply Aristotelian logic to the world-processes and thus grasp their nature by way of the intellect.

Socrates and Plato were the first thinkers who, instead of symbolizing the perceptions of the supersensible, transformed them into concepts. Aristotle developed the conceptual activity of the spirit (mind) and attempted to apply it to knowledge of the sense-world, within this world itself. It was not long before the agonizing question arose: Is knowledge of this kind able to bring us into connection with the original foundation of the world? (Scepticism – Pyrrho, 360-270 B.C.) The agnosticism of our time has its roots in the skepticism of the Ancient Greeks.

Anthroposophy brings the human being into a relationship to the concept, such that on the one side of it he meets the sense-world, and on the other side the spiritual world. One should beware of immediately seeing in this position an appeal to the mysticism of neo-Platonism. Conceptual thinking is regarded in Anthroposophy as an organism; it grows and embraces the soul in the complete fullness of its life, not closing it off in abstraction but, on the contrary, enriching it with the reality of the world of spirit.

In his account of the nature of the concept, Rudolf Steiner suggests that we imagine an object that is blocking the path of the light and casting a shadow. This shadow is similar to the object in question and comes about because the light is shut out from a given volume of space. Something comparable to this phenomenon happens with concepts. When they are formed, a certain supersensible reality is shut out, and the concepts – like the shadows – resemble them, their “objects”. Hence, they bring to manifestation the supersensible in the sensible world, albeit in a very remarkable way. Where perception of the super- sensible shifts over into the sense-world a shadow-picture arises – the concept. There is contained in it as little supersensible reality as there is sense-reality, sense-perceptible object, in the shadow. The concept represents the boundary between two worlds, but this boundary is “drawn” from the side of the supersensible world.

When we think dialectically, we connect concepts with concepts, whereby we follow the law of their autonomous movement (in the way Hegel did). This law of theirs is a manifestation of the supersensible reality standing behind them. The concepts themselves embody so fine a material substance, that they are the most spiritual of all that man calls his own in the sense-world. It is not at all easy to grasp the super-sensible nature of concepts and ideas, yet it is in the highest degree necessary; the crisis of cognition bears eloquent witness to this need. We can be helped in this undertaking by the evolutionistic research method of spiritual science.

* * *

The objectification of concepts, their severance from their connections with the world-whole, occurs not only by way of the cultural-historical process of development. This separation is prepared for by the spiritual-organic becoming of man, which, projected onto the cultural-historical process, continues right up to the present day, albeit in a weakened form. Its peculiar feature consists in the fact that, as it unfolds, as Rudolf Steiner says, “a non-being in thinking” is released from sense-perceptible reality (B. 45, p.12).

From the mid-point of the earthly aeon, which coincides with the middle of the Atlantean root-race, universal consciousness separates off a part of the world-whole and sets it over against itself in the sphere of otherness, as a kingdom in which the life-principle (etheric principle) is absent. Finally there takes place a “separating off” of consciousness itself into the sphere of non-consciousness, if one regards consciousness from the standpoint of real being.

In its first half, the earthly aeon passed through a repetition of the three preceding aeons. First, the earth condensed out of the world-Spirit to the warmth condition, thereby becoming similar to Old Saturn. Out of this “primal fire” of the earth the foundation was created for the blood-system. Then air and light appeared and there emerged the first beginnings of breathing and the nervous system. At a later stage water arose; it was pervaded by tone, which caused the substances to “dance”. The most important formation arising from this “dance of the substances” is albumen, the foundation of all that is living*   (see GA 102, 16.3.1908). Actually, the main characteristic of the earthly stage of development was that living warmth became mineral. At that time there arose, parallel to the warmth metamorphosis, a process of combustion which resulted in the shedding of a certain material deposit – ‘ash’. In the planetary processes, those processes which take place in the course of the fourth globe on the scale of the entire solar system, this “shedding of the deposit” was the emergence of the mineral kingdom. This is how being was “separated off”. But as world-being, before the combustion process occurred, was the being of universal consciousness, the world was divided, with the forming of mineral substance – the “ash” which pervaded all living entities in the sense-world – into non-being and world-consciousness. In the human being the process of mineralization was closely connected with the rhythmical system: with breathing and blood circulation. Breathing takes place on all levels of being. It is a multiplicity of forms of cosmic rhythm, but also of forms of relationship between beings and their surroundings and of beings amongst themselves. All human perceptions are a refined form of breathing. At first, man developed the process of breathing-perception supersensibly. He lived at that time, nourished by the revelations and within the revelations of exalted spiritual beings. When he had acquired the capacity to breathe air, he began, parallel to the supersensible perceptions, to “breathe in” all that had come into being apart from these – his sense organs were opened up to the external world. “Absolute longing” in the human being became the wish for the sense world, desire. He turned his inner life towards the sense-world, and his breath forfeited its spiritual content.

* In the books and lectures of Rudolf Steiner all these processes are described from many angles and with a wealth of detail
______

Rudolf Steiner describes this transition as follows: “But just as in the head there is taken up by the sense-perceptions the breath-process that streams into the body, so is taken up by the rest of the body that which streams outwards as outbreathed air. In the limb-metabolic organism there stream together the bodily feelings, our experiences with the outbreathed air, just as the sense-perceptions stream into the head through what we hear and into the exhilarating element of the inbreathed air through what we see. The sobering quality of the outbreathed air, that which extinguishes perception, all this streamed together with the bodily feelings aroused by walking and by work. Doing things outwardly, actively, this was connected with the outbreathing. And as the human being engaged in activity.... he felt as though the spiritual-soul element was flowing away from him.... as though he was letting the spiritual-soul element stream into the things. .... But this perception of the outbreathing.... of the sobering process came to an end, and there was only a trace of it left in the Greek times. In Greek times human beings still felt as though, when they were outwardly active, they were giving something spiritual to things. But then all that was there in the breathing process was depleted by bodily feeling, by the feeling of exertion, of tiredness in work” (GA 211, 26.3.1922).

The inbreathing process was “impaired” in the head, and what was left of the former inbreathing process which led into the spiritual and had then been “impaired” by the outer sense-perceptions, one began to call “Sophia”; those who wished to devote themselves to this Sophia were known as philosophers. The word “philosophy”, so Rudolf Steiner remarks, points to the “inner experience”.

The outbreathing process which was “impaired” through the feeling of the bodily nature became “pistis”, faith. “Thus wisdom and faith flowed together in the human being. Wisdom streamed to the head, faith lived in the whole human being. Wisdom was the content of ideas, and faith was the strength of this ideal content.... In the Sophia one (had) a rarefaction of the inbreathing, and in faith one had a densification of the outbreathing.... Then wisdom was rarefied still further. And in this extended rarefaction wisdom became science” (ibid.).

The process described by Rudolf Steiner took many thousands of years; it was accompanied by a whole series of physiological and other processes, a particularly important role being played here by the acquisition of the power of speech. When man did not yet have the power of articulate speech, he was able to understand the sounds of nature. This was in the Old Atlantean epoch. After that time the half-supersensible perception of the language of nature grew ever weaker. The human being developed speech organs, acquired the gift of speech and began to understand the meaning of words, and this is ultimately what drove the “ash” “physically-chemically” into the elements of his body. The bony skeleton began to form in the body, and as this emerged, so the intellect began to dawn. But before all this happened, the coarsening of perception which occurred in the Lemurian epoch after the opening of the sense-organs to the external world, brought with it a qualitative decline of the processes in the circulatory system of the blood. The nervous system, too, became mineral, “physical-chemical”, but as this happened it took over the former spiritual breathing – astral breathing. Because sense-perceptions had grown unusually strong, their influence caused us to lose the faculty of experiencing the breathing process consciously. In ancient times the human being, when he breathed in, perceived within himself the spiritual content of the object and carried out his observation in this way; in his outbreathing he surrendered the feeling of the spiritual and felt within himself a strengthening of the will-impulse – he carried out an action. Today, the impulse of outer perception, through stimulation of the nerve, reaches through to the blood circulation and has an effect upon it, which then passes over into the whole organism, including the metabolism. A portion of the material substance falls out of the organic process and the life of the inner representations arises as a result.

A yoga pupil attempts to restore to the breathing process its ancient function, to make it conscious, free from the forming of sense-impressions and, using the breath as a vehicle, to reunite in spirit with cosmic wisdom – “to become one with Brahma”. But the human being of the West, says Rudolf Steiner, has all of this “already in his concepts and ideas. It is really so: Shankaracharya would present to the pupils who revere him, the idea world of Soloviev, Hegel and Fichte as the beginning of the ascent to Brahma” (GA 146, 5.6.1913).

On his descent into earthly incarnation, the human being forms himself out of the forces of cosmic thought. But on the earth the universe surrounds him with sense-impressions and lives reflected in his thinking. The outer world in its influence upon man tends to condition and compel him in the same way as, in the past, he was influenced by spiritual-supersensible forces. If the human being were merely to reflect the outer world, he would be subjected by it to the laws of its inorganic realm, in which the laws of the universal spirit come to expression (are reflected) in the most ideal way. In such a case, says Rudolf Steiner, our lungs, convolutions of the brain etc. would have assumed crystal-line form. But the life of our organism opposes such tendencies. “And this activity of resistance accounts for the fact that, instead of imitating with our organs the forms of these earthly surroundings, we merely copy them in shadow pictures in our thoughts. Thus the power of thought is actually always tending to make of us an image of our physical earth, the physical form of the earth. ... But our organization does not allow this to happen...and so the images of the earthly forms only come about in geometry and whatever else we form in the way of thoughts of our earthly surroundings.... A table wants to make your brain itself into a table inside your head. You don’t allow this to happen. Thus arises within you the picture of the table” (GA 210, 17.2.1922).

* * *

Such is the interrelation of the two sides of reality, and their effect upon the human being who is placed between them in his earthly life. From this knowledge we can draw an understanding of the nature of human self-consciousness and of the self-conditioning capacity of the human being. Here the macro and micro-levels of being stand in the most direct mutual integration. In order to grasp their interplay as it is at the chronologically latest stage, we must look back at their primal origin, which we did in our account of the first act of the creation of the world by the three Logoi. When God had revealed Himself in three hypostases, He showed His counter-image in the creation. A process of ‘inwardization’ of the Creator in the creation took place, which was also the primal origin of the development of inner processes in the created world. Fundamentally speaking, the cosmos ‘inwardized’ itself in the processes of the human blood and nerves. The Divine will to sacrifice, to revelation, which created all the visible forms in the universe, brought about, after He had become, within the subject, absolute desire of (for) selfhood, that inversion which made the human being into an image in miniature of the cosmos – the microcosm.

Without radical opposition such a process is impossible. The Divine will which, in the human being, in his willing and feeling, sets itself over against itself, becomes desire and takes on an egocentric character. To a certain degree this robs the creation of its meaning; it begins to die, to be shed like withered leaves from the universal reality. It is not easy to imagine how the egocentric tendencies of the human monads led to the emergence of the entire universe that is visible to the senses, but it is nevertheless true. Before it acquired individual ‘I’- consciousness the human monad was a macrocosmic being. It was a combination of different strivings of hierarchical Beings, whose shared goal it was, to create the ‘I’-being in the world of otherness. From a certain moment in development (it is marked by the Fall from Paradise) the human being was driven by desire – which became within him a Luciferic will to act – uncontrollably into the world of otherness (of not being), where finally the abstract concept was born – the form of consciousness which had entirely lost the relation to its spiritual, cosmic archetype. Intellectual thinking represents, as it were, “holes in the universe”. And when I think, says Rudolf Steiner, this means that I am not (cf. GA 343, p.434). In this state of being a strong individual will can, of course, arise; desire that is purified and freed from Luciferic arbitrariness is transformed into will of the individual spirit to attain freedom. And because, if we think in concepts, we dwell in the realm of non-being, there also arises in the universe a place for freedom of this kind, for the free motives of human activity.

With his concepts that are devoid of essential being, the human being was cast out to the periphery of the universe. There, particularly from the 15th century onwards (from the beginning of the consciousness-soul epoch), concepts lost the final traces of their perceptual character. Since that time one can restore it to them only by bringing the will into the thinking and into the process of sense-perception. The passive beholding of the imaginative world of the thought-beings by the Ancient Indians, which in the Egyptian passed through the stage of spiritualized thought-perception of the macrocosm, of its universal laws and their projection onto earthly being, became in the fifth cultural epoch the mathematical-mechanistic conception of the world (but beyond these conceptions the real world of cosmic thinking can open up to the human being). Having, himself, become ‘not-real’ in thinking, the human being attains a free relation to the real as to the object. One of these objects is he himself – the active object of self-knowledge. And “to know oneself as a deed-performing personality,” so Rudolf Steiner says, “means: to possess as knowledge the laws – i.e. the moral concepts and ideals – which correspond to one’s deeds. Once we have attained knowledge of these laws our action is also our own.... The object in this case is our own ‘I’.” Rudolf Steiner concludes from this: “To know the laws of one’s own action means to be conscious of one’s freedom. The cognitive process is, according to the argument presented here, the process of development to freedom” (GA 3, p.87 f.). There arises thus between the laws of pure spirit and the natural laws of the sense-perceptible universe, the world of the laws of the self- conditioned human individuality. As we are bringing to light the true nature of cognition in this way, we would also recall that the unitary foundation of being is shown to us in a threefold revelation: As the world of perceptions (both outer and inner), as absolute desire and as the world of thinking, in which the Holy Spirit strives to reflect back to the Father, in a pure form and in the ‘I’, the principle of His universal consciousness. Hence there is revealed in thinking that has freed itself from percepts in which the sense-world imposes its forms upon us, the entire foundation of being “in its most perfect form, as it is in and for itself” (GA 2, p.84). When we think, the Divine Ground of the world merges immanently with the process of thinking. It works within it not out of some kind of world beyond, but immediately, as within its own content. Over against this content of the Divine Ground there stands the world of experience as Its own manifestation, mediated by the process of development. A first consequence of this is, that “Through our think- ing we raise ourselves from the beholding of reality as a product to the beholding as a productive fact” (ibid.). A second consequence is that in the human being and through him God cognizes Himself in the act of creation.

Through acquainting himself with the laws of thinking and using them in his activity, the human being overcomes the death quality of the isolated concept. He brings dynamic into concepts, leads the one over into the other, metamorphoses them. Thus he awakens an – albeit still illusory – life of the conceptually thinking consciousness. As an outcome of this there arises pure thinking, which is not only free of all sensory content, but is also freed from the human organization itself (see chapter 9 of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’). It is now no longer the same thinking as that which had as its content the sum of the concepts called forth by perceptions. It frees itself from all experience of whatever kind, in order to reflect it back to the Father in the hypostasis of the Holy Spirit. Since it is a fruit of evolution, the whole of evolution is present within it in a preserved and yet superseded (aufgehoben) form: evolution constitutes its essential being. But essential being is always the ‘I’.

* * *

We have thus arrived at a kind of cyclic movement in the development of world and man. At its beginning, God, revealing Himself as three in one, gives the impulse, as an all-embracing idea of creation, to a cosmic cult in the course of which the higher Hierarchies who fulfill the will, the idea, of God offer up in love the gifts of sacrifice one after the other. The fruit of these is a new phenomenon in the universe – the human being. The world-idea is then incarnated in the human being. At the beginning of the earthly aeon the Holy Spirit, working through the creation to the Creator, brings about a ‘separation’ of sense-reality from man. This reality, at a later stage, confronts him from within and without in a form that grows increasingly complex. For this reason, as Rudolf Steiner says, everything that we rightly describe as our inner world also stands over against us in the outer world. All that we can experience inwardly is experienced by us together with (in connection with) the entire external world (see GA 191, 18.10.1919). We reflect thoughts, but the entire material world given to us in sensations and perceptions reflects our perceptions. In relation to us it is entirely similar to the brain, and we enter into a relation to it in the role of thought-beings, who use the support it provides and are reflected back from it through the astrality of our perceptions. ‘Thinking’ of this kind (external to ourselves) is not abstract; it is living and substantial, but not individualized like our conceptual thinking. As his ‘I’-consciousness grows in strength, the human being frees himself from this thinking of a super-individual, group nature into the non-being of abstractions. And yet their world possesses something that is, without doubt, of decisive importance for man. Rudolf Steiner speaks of this as follows: “As we only experience in thinking a real, lawful structure, an ideal determination (ideelle Bestimmtheit), the lawful structure of the rest of the world which we do not experience directly within this world, must also be contained in thinking. In other words: appearance as phenomenon for the senses and thinking stand over against each other in the world of our experience. However, the former provides us with no insight as to its essential nature; while the latter provides us with insight as to itself and, at the same time, as to the essential nature of the realm of appearance for the senses” (GA 2, p.48).

In other words, the essential nature of the thing can only be known through the thing being brought in relation to thinking consciousness. And the essential nature of the thing is the embodiment of the world- idea. To imagine that ideas exist in the heads of human beings is an illusion pure and simple. No, they hold sway as laws within the things. The Anthroposophical theory of knowledge maintains the standpoint that the universals of three kinds are merely different aspects of a single Idea. The division of the world into object and subject has, therefore, no more than a formal character. “The idea conceived by the primal Being could only be one that, by virtue of a necessity lying within itself, develops from within itself a content which then manifests in an- other form – in a ‘beheld’ form – in the world of appearance” (GA 1, p.108). The two forms of manifestation of the idea (as concept and percept) attain their full congruence in the human being.



3. ‘Sensory Appearance’ and ‘Thinking’ in the World-View of Ideal-Realism

The belief that the world is hopelessly divided for the cognizing subject into inner representation and ‘thing-in-itself’ has its source in religious and moral convictions of ancient times. It originates in that conception of development which is described figuratively in the Bible as the story of the Temptation and the expulsion of man from Paradise. It was at this time that what amounted to a confrontation between creation and Creator took place, and this gave rise to the preconditions for a dividing into two, of the creation’s experience of the world. Considerably later, in the Zoroastrian religion of the Persians, man began to experience the dualism of the world as the opposition between light and darkness, good and evil. The consciousness emerged in man, of his participation in the cosmic battle between the good and the evil Gods. In the Ancient Greek culture-epoch the religious conceptions are given philosophical expression, whereby the darkness of outer, sense-perceptible being stands opposed to the world of ideas coming from above. Also coloured by the heritage of the past is the dualism of the Christian view of life, in which the world of sensory, material reality is brought into connection with the picture and the idea of darkness and of sin, while the world of the prayer-illumined individual spirit is connected with the idea of salvation, of redemption from sin.

The whole of this, in a certain sense, ‘inherited’ dualism is overcome in the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’, first on the philosophical and then on the moral level. The human being is led to experience of the unitary world when he acquires the conceptual, moral intuitions – i.e. when he radically alters, spiritualizes the way he observes. To a certain extent, a return to the old takes place, but on a different, individual basis. The new human being has achieved this, at the price of his real and complete expulsion from Paradise. The Ancient Greek, however, who knew of the intuitive nature of thinking and morality, was still standing at the boundary between Paradise and earth. Parmenides, the founder of the Eleatic school, wrote a poem about a poet who travels along the boundary between two worlds and, as he does so, listens to the voice of a Goddess. She teaches him that true being exists only on the other side of the boundary, and that being on this side of the boundary is necessary, but deceptive.

Plato shared the position of the Eleatics. He divided conceptions of the world into two categories: the true one, which seeks its support in the world of ideas, and the other, which in its nature is apparent only, being conditioned by what is given through the sense-organs. Awareness of the fact that the world is revealed to the human being from two sides had enormous significance for the further development of the ‘I’- consciousness, but in the history of the development of thought in Western Europe, an error which then became universal sprang from the world-view of Plato. It consisted in the following question: What is the nature of the relation between the sense-world and the world of ideas outside the human being?

In his book ‘Goethe’s World-View’ Rudolf Steiner characterizes as follows the consequence of Plato’s world-view mentioned above: “Platonism is convinced that the goal of all striving for knowledge must be acquisition of the ideas which carry and constitute the foundation of the world” (GA 6, p.28). A sense-world that is not illumined by the world of ideas cannot be regarded as full reality. This was then interpreted to imply that “the sense-world in itself, quite apart from the human being, is a world of appearance, and true reality is only to be found in the ideas” (ibid.).

This position was also adopted without reservation by Spinoza, who subscribed to the view that only those thoughts possess true reality which arise independently of sense-perceptions. He extended this to the sphere of ethics, the moral feelings and actions of man; he maintained that ideas drawn from our perceptions originate solely in desires. The ascetic ethics of the Christian religious consciousness, with which that of Spinoza was in full harmony, also stemmed from a one-sidedly interpreted Platonism. Incidentally, Spinoza found a brilliant way out of this tragic error. He had the idea that one could raise intellectual development to such a height, that the human being would begin to experience in thinking the real manifestation of the spirit. In his letter to H. Oldenburg written in Nov. 1675 one can read the following: “... I (say) that for the sake of salvation it is not absolutely necessary to know Christ according to the flesh, but that the case is quite different with that eternal Son of God – i.e. with God’s eternal wisdom, which has been made manifest in all things, and mostly in the human spirit, and above all in Christ Jesus.”132 Here we have to do with the Christianized theosophy of Plato. Quite a different path was taken by Kant, who definitively undermined all hope of knowledge of the essential nature of things. The knowledge we have, so Kant believed, is not of the things in the world, but only of the impressions which, in some mysterious way, they make upon the human being. The world of experience does not exist objectively. It is we ourselves who create the connections within it. There exist truths which are of significance for the world of experience, but which are not dependent upon it and are not able to re- veal to us the essential nature of things.

With regard to this world-view of the Königsberg philosopher, Rudolf Steiner said of him that he was lacking in “the natural sense for the relationship between percept and idea”. One of the prejudices taken over by Kant from his predecessors, said Steiner, consisted in his acceptance of the view “that there are necessary truths which are engendered by pure thinking, free from all experience”. In support of his claim that there are such truths, Kant pointed to mathematics and pure physics. “Another prejudice of his consists in his denial of the ability of experience to arrive at equally necessary truths. Lack of trust in the world of perception is also present in Kant. In addition to these habits of thought we must also count the influence of Hume upon Kant.” This influence showed itself in Kant’s sympathy for Hume’s contention “that the ideas into which thinking draws together the single percepts do not stem from experience; thinking adds them to experience. These three prejudices form the roots of the Kantian thought-structure” (GA 6, p.40 ff.).

Rudolf Steiner compares the mistaken conceptions of Kant with the views of Plato, summarizing them as follows: “Plato clings to the world of ideas, because he believes that the true nature of the world must be eternal, indestructible, unchanging and he can only ascribe these qualities to the ideas. Kant is content merely to be able to attribute these qualities to the ideas. Then they no longer need to express the essential nature of the world at all” (ibid. p.43). Kant’s teacher Hume, for his part, regarded human ideas as being no more than habits of thought (thus anticipating Mach, undoubtedly). For him, only perceptions possessed reality. A similar position was also taken by the sensualists John Locke and Condillac, and even by openly materialistic thinkers, from Lamettrie and Holbach onwards. The advance of Platonism in the modern age can be traced in a sequence of world-views extending from Spinoza to Hegel. For Hegel, thought-activity is an objective creation of the soul. Rudolf Steiner compares the role of Hegel in modern times with that of Plato in the ancient Greek period. Plato, so he says, “lifts his spiritual gaze to the world of ideas and lets this gaze in its beholding grasp hold of the mystery of the soul; Hegel lets the soul dive down into the world-Spirit, and then, after it has dived down, he lets it unfold its inner life. The soul thus lives as its own life what the world-Spirit lives into which it has dived down” (GA 18, vol. 1).

The whole world, so Hegel believes, is filled with the Divine, i.e. with thought; God is an organism consisting of the totality of all ideas, but of those ‘before the things’ and not those that are reflected back in the human head; it was, in deed and truth, from the former that nature was created; the human being developed on the basis of this thought and it is his mission that in him thought should be revealed in its highest form – as the essential nature of things; the evolution of the world, the history of culture is ultimately nothing other than the development of the idea: first of all in ‘being-in-itself’ – i.e. before the created world, then in ‘otherness-of-being’ – i.e. in nature, and finally in ‘being-for-itself’ – in the human soul in history, in the State; in the highest phase of its development the idea comes to itself in art, religion and philosophy – in the first two through the mediation of image and symbol, but immediately in philosophy. “In Hegel,” says Rudolf Steiner, “one can find a pure thinker who wishes to approach the task of solving the riddles of the world, by way of reason alone, free of all mysticism” (GA 20, p.49). He rejects mysticism as a source of metaphysics, but only to let it rise up again in the theosophy of philosophy.* Rudolf Steiner asks what is the purpose, in Hegel, of “our life in the ideas of (pure) reason? It is so that the human soul can submit in devotion to the supersensible cosmic forces that hold sway within it. This becomes a genuine mystical experience.... It is mysticism ... when the soul wrestles its way out of the darkness of the personal soul-life, up into the luminous clarity of the world of ideas” (ibid.). Nothing comparable to this can be found either in Fichte or in Schelling – two of the most notable representatives of German idealism. But what unites them all is the striving to confine themselves exclusively to the realm of the conceptual. Yes, it is true that Hegel frees logic, as it were, from the gravity of earth, but it remains, all the same, a logic of purely conceptual thinking and contains within it nothing that would contribute to a stepping across the boundary of the abstract into the supersensible world of ideas, of which Plato spoke. In his apologia of the world of thought, so Rudolf Steiner tells us, Hegel actually caused terrible confusion. He described “the necessity of thought as being, at the same time, the necessity of fact ... he thereby gave rise to the mistaken view that the determinations of thinking are not purely ideal, but factual”. But one must emphasize, Rudolf Steiner continues, “that the domain of thinking is solely human consciousness”, but “this circumstance does not cause the thought-world to forfeit its objectivity in any way.... We must imagine two things: one is that we bring the ideal world to manifestation through our activity, and that at the same time, what we actively call into existence rests upon its own laws” (GA 2, p.51 f.).

* Not, however, in the philosophy of theosophy.
______

Anthroposophical philosophy shares the position of German idealism, but avoids its mistakes and enhances it through the addition of two essential elements. As to its mistakes, these are described by Rudolf Steiner with remarkable clarity and conciseness in one of his note-books: “Schelling was mistaken about nature, not because he sought the spirit in it, but because there is in it more spirit than he could find, because he tried to encompass the spirit of nature in the mere reflected image of the spirit, which lies in human thought. Instead of the beholding of nature – the creating of nature. (Schelling maintained that to philosophize about nature means to create nature – G.A.B.) Fichte was mistaken about the human being, not because he sought man’s essential nature in the act of self-willing, but because he was not able to let the whole human being arise out of the creative will, only the idea of the human being. – Instead of devotion to the world-Spirit – fetishism of logic” (Beiträge 30, p.19). With regard to the additional elements needed by Middle-European philosophical idealism, Anthroposophy sees the first of these in the solving of its own riddle. The representatives of what Rudolf Steiner calls the ‘forgotten’ streams of idealism came very close indeed to its solution. They included the younger Fichte, Immanuel Hermann (a successor of Schelling), the Swiss doctor and philosopher I.P.V. Troxler, Karl Christain Plank (1819-1880) and others. This riddle – or mystery, Rudolf Steiner says, consists in the fact that “German idealism...” points to “the germinal force of a real development of those cognitive powers in man which see the supersensible-spiritual just as the senses see the sensory material” (GA 20, p.63).

A further addition through which German idealism was enhanced by Anthroposophy consisted in the solution to the question how one should view the relation of the idea to sense-reality. Vast amounts of energy were wasted, especially in the school of Leibniz-Kant, in the search for a way to attain, in purely conceptual thought, knowledge of the essential nature of things without reference to the data of experience. Meanwhile, at the opposite pole of world-views, work was being done on the development of the experimental sciences – in which the human being was simply lost sight of – and of the philosophy of material immanentism, where everything culminates in the conviction: “Once man has researched all the properties of the material substances which are able to make an impression on his developed senses, then he has grasped the essential nature of things. He thereby attains what is for him – i.e. for humanity – absolute knowledge. For the human being, no other knowledge exists” (Jacob Moleschott, 1851). 133

In the final analysis, philosophy as a whole can be divided into two great trends, whereby the criterion one takes is the relation to idea and perception. One trend can be characterized as a kind of universal Platonism, which extends from its founder to the medieval mystics and classical German idealism and from there to the Russian Sophiologists (V. Soloviev, Andrei Beliy, Pavel Florenski etc.). Common to all these thinkers is the striving to help thought to achieve a position of domination. For them, knowledge of the idea is the knowledge (Wissenschaft) of what truly is. While one cannot say that these thinkers ignore sense reality, they do underestimate it and are often at a loss to know what to do with it.

The other fundamental trend in philosophy can be seen as proceeding from Aristotle. This is the stream of realism. To illustrate its essential character, we can refer back to what Rudolf Steiner says about Aristotle in ‘The Riddles of Philosophy’: “Aristotle wishes to dive down into beings and processes, and what the soul finds in this act of diving down, is for him the essential nature of the thing itself. The soul feels as if it has only raised this essential nature out of the thing and brought it into the form of thought, in order to be able to carry this with it as a memory of the things. Thus, for Aristotle the ideas are in the things and processes; they are the one side of the things, that side which the soul, through the means available to it, can raise out of them; the other side, which the soul cannot raise out of the things, and through which they have their own self-contained life, is substance, matter” (GA 18, vol. 1).

Aristotle develops the doctrine of the threefold soul. In this, he investigates – in contrast to Plato, for whom only that in the soul is important which, within it, lives and shares in the life of the spirit – how the knowledge it acquires stands over against the soul, and in a different way towards each one of its parts (this question is also dealt with by Rudolf Steiner). In his outline of the riddles of the ancient Greek philosophy, Rudolf Steiner says in this connection: According to Aristotle, the soul must “also dive down into itself in order to find within itself that which constitutes its essential nature.... The idea has its reality, not in the cognizing soul, but combined with the material substance (hyle) in the external thing. If, however, the soul dives down into itself it finds the idea as such in reality. The soul is, in this sense, idea, but active idea, it is effectively working being. And also in a human life it acts as an effectively working being. In the germinal life of the human being it takes hold of the bodily nature. Whereas in the case of an inanimate thing idea and matter form an inseparable unity, in the case of the human soul and its body this is not so. Here, the autonomous human soul takes hold of the bodily nature, makes ineffective the idea that is already active in the body, and puts itself in its place. ... A body that bears within it the soul nature of the plant and the animal is, as it were, fertilized by the human soul, and thus, for earthly man, a bodily-soul element is united with a spiritual-soul element. ... Aristotle finds the idea within the thing; and the soul attains within the body what it is meant to be as an individuality in the spiritual world” (ibid.).

The philosophy of Aristotle found its true continuation in Thomas Aquinas’ doctrine of the universals; when it became the foundation for the world-views that were dominant in the 20th century, it assumed a positivist and purely materialistic form. In time, the Aristotelian understanding of the material world as consisting not only of matter but also of substance, which underlies reality as a spiritual element, was abandoned as being no longer usable.

The world-views of idealism and realism in their overall phenomenology possess decisive significance for the development of the individual spirit to freedom. There comes to expression in them an orientation towards the higher ‘I’ and the lower ‘I’ (cf. Fig.35). In its movement towards the higher ‘I’, the individual spirit finds its true development, its truth, which is contained within the monism of ideal-realism. But in order to be able to reach through to this, one must first become familiar with its two component elements: the nature of human experience, which is given in the perception of the outer world, and also the inner world of the soul; and the (for the human being) deductive anticipation of experience in the world of the intelligible Beings.



4. Goethe, Hegel and Rudolf Steiner

Towards the end of the 19th century the maturity had been reached of the objective conditions for the uniting of the two general trends in the development of views of the world – idealism and realism. But first the capacity of consciousness to transcend the limits of the merely conceptual needed to be demonstrated through the medium of pure philosophy. Eduard von Hartmann tried to do this through an appeal to the unconscious, and Rudolf Steiner through an appeal to the super- conscious.

Already at the end of the 18th century, Goethe had been in a certain sense a precursor of the great synthesis. He understood that the question of the relation between idea and sense-world, of how the idea and the things of the senses can find one another – a question to which European thinkers had devoted so much attention – cannot be asked out- side the human being, but that their synthesis is only possible in the human being, and not by way of thinking alone or of observation alone.

The cognitive principle developed by Goethe rejects that part of Aristotle’s teaching which speaks of the attainment of self-knowledge through diving down into one’s own soul. Nor did Goethe wish to sink with his individual spirit into the world-Spirit, but only into the world of experience; for then, so he believed, one would also acquire the idea. For Goethe, the world of experience also contains within it the world of ideas; for this reason, so he asserts, it is incorrect to say “experience and idea”. Of course, the idea cannot be perceived with one’s ordinary sense-organs; it is accessible to spiritual experience, spiritual perception, but perception nevertheless, and in just as real a way as sense-objects are accessible to sense-perception. This was the view of Goethe, which formed the basis of his gnoseology and was so new that it was hardly understood by anyone until the end of the 19th century, when Rudolf Steiner gave a description and commentary on it, where-upon the scientific world treated it with barely concealed hostility.*

* Recently the plan has been made in Germany to publish a new edition of Goethe’s scientific works and replace Rudolf Steiner’s commentary with an- other, thereby obscuring Goethe’s method.
______

In his article ‘Concerning the Gain for our View of Goethe’s Scientific Work, arising from the Publications of the Goethe Archive’, which appeared in the 1891 edition of the Goethe Yearbook, Rudolf Steiner wrote the following: “He (Goethe) did not wish only to observe what is accessible to sense-perception; he strove at the same time towards a spiritual content which allowed him to determine the essential nature of the objects of this perception. This spiritual content through which a thing emerged for him out of the dullness of sense-existence, out of the indeterminacy of external beholding, and became something clearly determined in its nature (animal, plant, mineral) was called by Goethe Idea” (GA 30, p.270).

According to Goethe, the idea is not identical with sense-experience in its immediately given character, and true cognition consists in distancing oneself from this. On the other hand, Goethe does not, so Rudolf Steiner says in his book ‘Goethe’s World-View’, appreciate “any theory that wishes to be conclusive once and for all and is meant in its existing form to represent an eternal truth. He wishes to have living concepts through which the spirit of the individual draws together in his own individual manner the way things are beheld**  (emphasis G.A.B.). To know the truth means, for Goethe, to live in the truth. And to live in the truth is nothing else than to take note, in the observation of every single thing, of what inner experience arises when one is standing before this thing. Such a view of human cognition cannot speak of limits of knowledge, of its being restricted by the nature of the human being” (GA 6, p.66 f.).

** This corresponds to the sixth element in our sevenfold lemniscate of the thought-cycle.
________

Such, therefore, was Goethe’s answer to the fundamental question posed by Kant: What is knowledge? Goethe substantiated his answer through his own experience, as he had, on a practical level, developed within himself the capacity of ideal perception, of ‘beholding’. This is only possible if one metamorphoses the instrument of thinking into an instrument of ideal perception. In this way, Goethe laid the foundation, through transforming himself in practice, for that gigantic metamorphosis of the human species, thanks to which world-evolution enters a quite new phase. Rudolf Steiner was able to describe this event from the standpoint of modern science and in a scientifically comprehensible manner.

And he did not content himself with merely giving a description. Through incorporating Goethe’s teaching into its methodological foundation, Anthroposophy goes considerably further than Goethe himself. This is evident from its content as a whole. In the same book, ‘Goethe’s World-View’, Rudolf Steiner speaks of this himself when he compares Goethe with Hegel. Hegel felt himself to be a philosopher of a thoroughly Goethean kind, as one may clearly gather from a letter he wrote to Goethe on the 20th Feb. 1821. The affinity of the two thinkers’ ideas is seen in their approach to the principle of metamorphosis. In his observations Goethe came right up to the boundary where the sensible-supersensible phenomena of the plant-world are revealed and the idea comes towards the researcher. And yet: “In what relation the ideas stand to one another; how within the ideal realm the one proceeds out of the other; these are tasks of investigation which only begin on the empirical height where Goethe advances no further” (ibid. p.205).

According to Goethe, the multiplicity of manifested forms of the idea can be traced back to a fundamental form, a unitary idea, since they are all identical in their true and essential nature. So Goethe thought, but he left to the philosophers the solution of this problem. And Hegel was a philosopher who did research into the metamorphosis of ideas, as they move from their “purely abstract being to the stage where the idea becomes immediate and real manifestation. He sees as this highest stage the phenomenon of philosophy itself, since it is in philosophy that the ideas which work actively in the world are beheld in their own original form” (ibid, p.206). But Hegel had, just as little as Goethe, access to the immediate, imaginative perception of the ideas; neither of them even considered it. Rudolf Steiner concludes that the very fact “that Hegel sees in philosophy the most perfect metamorphosis of the idea, proves that he is as far removed as Goethe is from true self-observation.... But philosophy contains the ideal content of the world, not in the form of life, but in the form of thoughts. The living idea, the idea as percept, is given to human self-observation alone” (emphasis G.A.B.) (ibid). The shortcomings in the world-views of Goethe and Hegel were remedied by Rudolf Steiner through the new step taken by him in the theory of knowledge, which (in addition to much else) he illustrated in the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. He combined his argument in favour of the principle of freedom from presupposition in epistemology, with self-observation, suggesting to those who wish it, that they should repeat his experience themselves and grasp the far-reaching consequences arising from it. Firstly, a metamorphosis of consciousness begins to take place in the subject of cognition, leading to the development of a thought-sense which makes possible for him an immediate perception of the idea. And secondly, the process described leads to the resolving of the question as to how consciousness can be imbued with being, thus enabling – and this is the third point – human freedom to begin.

Without insight into the innermost essence of the world of ideas, neither Goethe nor Hegel was able to develop a view concerning human freedom. For this reason Max Stirner reproached them for their “glorification” of the dependency of the subject upon the object. Rudolf Steiner has shown how the content of the world can find its highest expression in the human personality. But in order to understand this rightly, one must first remain for some time on the heights of Goethe’s and Hegel’s achievement and experience the non-completion of their search. In one of his lectures Rudolf Steiner says the significant words: “....we can best find our way into this modern spiritual life if we try, through using the instrument of Hegel, to encompass the great spirit and the great soul of Goethe” (GA 113, 28.8.1909). In the conditions of our own time the best approach for us is to use Hegel and Goethe as instruments with which “to encompass” the teaching of Rudolf Steiner.



5. The Natural-Scientific Method of Goethe and Rudolf Steiner

Regarding Goethe’s natural-scientific research it can also be said that it is methodologically free of prejudice. The method it applies is in the fullest sense of the word immanent to the object of study and free from conceptions and prescriptions that are dogmatic and have no root in experience. In his commentary to this research of Goethe, Rudolf Steiner draws out of it at least three methods. The first of them he calls “universal empiricism”. In accordance with this, Goethe remains in connection with the phenomenon and does not go beyond the limits of what is immediately given. This method requires one to give a precise description of the single particulars of the phenomenon. Goethe the researcher, who wishes to bring to light the causal connection between the phenomena, then moves across from universal empiricism to rationalism. He regarded both of these methods as limited and one-sided. The researcher has to use them to a certain extent, but then he must overcome them and apply the method of ‘rational empiricism’ which works with pure phenomena, these being identical with the laws of nature. The essence of this method is characterized as follows: “Because the objects of nature are separate from one another as phenomena, the synthesizing capacity of the spirit is needed, to show their inner unity. Because the unity of the understanding for itself is empty, the understanding must fill this unity with the objects of nature. Thus, in this third phase (the methodological – G.A.B.), phenomenon and spiritual capacity come to meet each other, and merge into one; and only this can bring full satisfaction to the spirit” (GA 1, p.190).

In his Goethe commentary, Rudolf Steiner built up at the same time his own methodology, in which the above-mentioned rational empiricism was able to unfold with a vigour unattainable to Goethe. From the beginning Rudolf Steiner places the main emphasis on the immediately given as the “what” of research, and not on the compliance with formal-methodological criteria. Scientific method betrays itself, when it places its reliance on abstract principles, sets itself unnecessary limits, and wrongly extends the monistic world-view into the sphere of methodology. Rudolf Steiner says of his own method: “Our standpoint is idealism, because it sees the ground of the world in the idea; it is realism, because it addresses the idea as what is real; and it is positivism or empiricism, because it wishes to reach the content of the idea not through construction a priori, but through approaching it as a given datum of experience. We have an empirical method which penetrates what is real and attains its final satisfaction in an idealistic result of research.... In our thinking there already presses up toward us what we wish to add to the immediately given. We must therefore reject any kind of metaphysics. Metaphysics wishes to explain the given with the help of something not-given, something inferred (Wolf, Herbart)” (ibid. p.182 f.).

Only a mind that is mistrustful of concepts will suspect that there is something eclectic in such an approach to the methodology of research, and only a consciousness that is free of prejudice will recognize the immense possibilities contained in it. When we have grasped it theoret- ically, only half our work is done. The method reveals its power through the realization of a certain cognitive experience, which does not, of course, in any way exempt us from the task of understanding the method itself.

Parallel to his commentary on the natural-scientific works of Goethe, Rudolf Steiner wrote the book ‘Outline of a Theory of Knowledge of the Goethean World-View’. This stands in the same relation to the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ as, for example, Hegel’s ‘Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences’ to his great work, the ‘Logic’, if we may venture the comparison. With regard to what we have said about the methodological principles of Anthroposophy, one can read in Rudolf Steiner’s book the following: “Thinking has access to that side of reality, of which a being of mere sense-perception would never have any experience.... Perception through the senses presents us with only one side of reality. The other side is the comprehension of the world by means of thinking.” “When we bring our thinking into activity, only then does reality receive its true determination (Bestimmungen)” (GA 2, p.63, 66). This should not lead us to think that we have to do with two sources of knowledge. There is only one such source, and that is experience in a wider sense, as the mediator between the subject, which feels the need to stand over against sense-experience in thinking, and the object, which is revealed to the outer senses; here, the subject can, in the process of spiritual, cognitive activity, raise itself to the experience that it is revealing itself to itself. And the ascent through the stages of cognition can become an ascent through the levels of consciousness.

General empiricism is the method we use in our work with the experience of direct sense-perceptions – sound, smell etc. And in this situation we feel that we are standing with our thinking over against our experience. It would be more exact to say here that the subject stands in the middle between the experience of perceptions and thinking about it. In this position, the subject applies the method of rational empiricism and, with its help, discovers ideal connections between the objects of perception. Knowledge of the connections ascends through different levels (cf. Fig.2); it leads us up to knowledge of the law governing the phenomenon. For this reason the concept is an element that belongs as intrinsically to the sense-world as its other parts, although, unlike these, it does not come to outer manifestation. “Sense-perception is therefore not a totality, but only one side of a totality. It is that side which can merely be looked at. Only through the concept does it become clear what it is that we are looking at” (GA 1, p.281).

In his striving to gain knowledge of the essential nature of things, the agnostic places this behind the things. Thus arises the limits to knowledge. But when we think about the things, we merge together with their essential being; they no longer stand outside us. But in this case, all that the human being says about the essential nature of things is revealed in the world of his own spiritual experiences. This person or that might accuse this methodological position of anthropomorphism; but here one could also appeal to the authority of Locke, who described as objective the primary qualities of things, which (as opposed to the secondary qualities such as colour, taste etc.) one can count and measure: they are all anthropomorphic. The human being humanizes his inner representations of nature, in very truth. But only in this way does the inner nature of things acquire the capacity to express itself. On the other hand we need to realize that the subjective qualities, too, are “nevertheless the expression of the inner essence of the things” (ibid. p.337). For this reason there is no basis for the assertion that an objective truth, the ‘in-itself’ of the things, is unknowable. The truth, in so far as it is known by the human being, cannot but be subjective. But now the objective nature of the things is revealed to the perceptions of our senses; they now appear to us as they really are. Hence, Goethe says: “The senses do not deceive.” But we can wrongly interpret our sense-experiences. To understand such a reversal, in Anthroposophy, of the generally accepted concepts, we need to avoid the pitfall of the theory of sense-experience, which consists in the intention to place “everything of a perceptible nature either within the soul” or “outside the soul” (B. 34). Locke’s school of thought severed the living connection between man and nature. It deprived nature of all those qualities by means of which it makes itself known directly to the human soul, and hid them away within the soul; and as time went on it fell into a state of tragic uncertainty, as it could find no answer to the question: What is the actual source of these secondary qualities that arise within me?

In his essay ‘Goethe and natural-scientific Illusionism’, which is added as a commentary in Vol. III of the natural-scientific works of Goethe, Rudolf Steiner says: “The subjectivity can, of course, be determined by nothing other than itself. Anything that cannot be shown to be conditioned by the subject, should not be described as ‘subjective’. We must now ask ourselves: What can we describe as belonging inherently to the human subject? All that it can experience in relation to itself (an sich selbst) through outer or inner perception.... Actually, what is subjective is only the path that has to be travelled by the sensation before it can be spoken of as my sensation. Our organization communicates the sensation, and these paths of communication are subjective; but the sensation itself is not” (GA 1, p.255 f.). And nothing gives us the right to assert that we create sensations.

If we have received some impression or other through the medium of eye or ear, we can investigate various mechanical, chemical and other processes which follow this impression outside or also within our- selves. They all take their course in space and time. “I can,” says Rudolf Steiner, “certainly ask myself: What spatio-temporal processes are taking place in this thing while it is displaying to my vision (let us say) the attribute of the colour red?” These processes have the character of a movement, electric currents etc.; something analogous occurs in the nerves, in the brain. “What is conveyed along this entire path is the percept of red which we have just referred to. How this percept expresses itself in a given thing that lies somewhere on the path from the excitant to the perception, depends entirely upon the nature of the thing in question. The sensation is present at every place, from the excitant to the brain, but not as such, not become explicit, but in precisely the way that corresponds to the nature of the object situated at that place.” Thus I experience “nothing more than the way in which that thing responds to the action proceeding from the sensation, or in other words: how a sen- sation comes to expression in a given object of the spatio-temporal world (emphasis G.A.B.). It is by no means the case that a spatio- temporal process of this kind is the cause that produces the sensation in me....” The process is, itself, “the effect of the sensation within a spatio-temporally extended thing”. The sensation comes to expression, as it were, in all processes of the sense-world; as such it does not exist in this world “because it simply cannot be there. But in those processes I do not, in any way, have as a given factor the objective nature of the processes of sensation; I have only a form in which they come to mani- festation”. And the processes themselves which convey the sensations are also given to us as sensations – in perception. Thus “the perceived world is... nothing other than a sum of metamorphosed percepts”. The perceived thing itself brings a sensation to expression in the manner “that corresponds to its nature. Strictly speaking, the thing is nothing other than the sum of those processes in the form of which it manifests” (ibid. p.267 ff.).

Such, therefore, is the fundamental picture drawn by Anthroposophy of the nature of sense-perception, and it forms the basis of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. There is full agreement between this and those statements in the philosophical system of Nikolai Losski in which he deals with sense-impressions. He says: “According to intuitivism, the object that is visible to an observer (a cloud) is an extract from the trans-subjective world itself (the cloud itself in the original), which has, itself, entered the subject’s horizon of consciousness; the colour of the cloud is not a soul-condition of the observer, but an attribute of the cloud itself, the trans-subjective. There is no such thing as a substitution of the material object by a soul-picture in the mind of the observer, hence no riddling problem arises as to the transformation of material into soul processes.”134

In another essay included in the third volume of Goethe’s Natural- Scientific Works, Rudolf Steiner approaches from a still wider perspective the question of the nature of perception. To counter the possible accusation that he had taken sides with Heraclitus and thus forgotten the “enduring element within change”, the “thing-in-itself” existing permanently behind the world of percepts, “lasting matter”, he says there that we would need to introduce the category of time into our considerations and separate, within the percept, the content from the form of its appearance. In the sensation given to the subject they are merged into one, as there is no sensation without a content. And sensations take place in the flow of time, but in such a way that their content – i. e. the enduring, objective factor – has nothing to do with time. The important element in the percept is not the fact that something occurs at a given point in time, but the question what is occurring. The sum total of the determinations (Bestimmungen) expressed in all these ‘whats’ forms the content of the world. The different ‘whats’ enable us to recognize connections of various kinds in their different forms of manifestation and they condition one another reciprocally in space and time. This fact gives rise to the wish to conceive, behind the sum-total of events, something unchanging – unending, indestructible matter. “But time is not a vessel in which the changes take place; it is not there before the things and outside them. Time is the expression, within the sense-world, of the circumstance that factual events, from the point of view of their content, are dependent upon one another in a (temporal) sequence” (GA 1, p.272 f.).

We discover time thanks to the fact that the essential being of some- thing comes to manifestation. “Time belongs to the world of appearance.” But it has “nothing to do” with the essential being itself. “This essential being can only be grasped ideally (in the form of ideas)” (ibid. p.273). If we have not understood this, we feel the need to hypostatize time as a factor in the unfolding of processes, and then an existence appears, which is able to outlast all changes: indestructible matter. But in reality the only thing that is indestructible is the essential being of the phenomenon (time itself is conditioned by it).*  135 Therefore in his other work – ‘Goethe’s World-View’ – Rudolf Steiner arrives at the conclusion that the “truth (and by implication also the essential nature of things – G.A.B.) arises through the interpenetration of percept and idea in the human cognitive process... there lives within the subjective that which is objective in the truest and deepest sense” (emphasis G.A.B.) (GA 6, p.64). Rudolf Steiner goes on to quote the following words of Goethe: “When the healthy nature of man works as a totality, when he feels himself in the world as within a great, beautiful, noble and valued whole, when harmonious satisfaction grants him a delight that is free and pure, then the universe, if it could experience itself, would jubilate at having attained its goal, and wonder at the pinnacle of its own becoming and being.”136

* In this connection it is interesting to note that Kant, in his search for the a priori principles of sense-experience, thought that time is “the form of the inner sense, i.e. of beholding of our self and our inner state.” It is subjective, but deducible from experience, and represents the a priori formal condition of all phenomena. Thus Kant virtually robs us in two ways of the possibility of ascending from appearance to essential being and takes refuge in metaphysics. This problem cannot be solved if we do not rise from the phenomenon to the ‘ur’-phenomenon.
________



6. The Subject of Cognition

The desire for knowledge arises in the human being and not out of the things around him. But when the human being is engaged in cognition, he is seeking, not for the ‘in-itself’ of things that will remain forever hidden from him, but for the balancing-out of two forces which approach him from two sides – through percepts and concepts. Without the human being such a process is impossible. How it should be carried out correctly, is a question dealt with by the Goethean theory of knowledge, which sees in this process the highest stage and the completion of the nature-process that has led to the forming of the individual principle within the world of otherness-of-being.

The act of cognition would not be necessary if the human being received something finished and complete through perception and observation. We observe a sequence of facts as something given; and moreover we come to know it in its givenness. But another, yet higher power of our spirit must reveal itself, so that the unending sequence of facts can be revealed on the level of the highest laws at work within them. And that which reveals itself in us in this case is a part of nature, only we create it ourselves. Thus we do not create the tone, the colour – they belong to outer nature and are objective – but we do create a higher, ideal part of nature.

The assertion that the world is nothing more than my inner representation has its source in the dominant role of the secondary qualities in our soul-life, and in an underestimation of the role of thinking in it. This assertion could be complemented by another: namely, that the human being is an inner representation of the world (the world-individual) with respect to the world’s primary qualities. For the sense-perceptions of the human being are not given to the world-subject. But the human being is able to have both kinds of inner representations and in this way to attain to a unitary reality, which is given in thinking and perception. Geometrical (spatial) and other mathematical conceptions, the ideas of force, of gravity – all these are observed by the human spirit which ‘beholds’ the ideal relations between the percepts. They are, as the medieval Scholastic would have said, “the essential forms within things”, from which they are liberated thanks to the human spirit. But in this case there can be no doubt that the human being as an inner representation of the world is also the “thing-in-itself” of this world, if the world has the capacity to know itself (and it has).

As regards the world that is given to man in his perceptions, we have here to do with the essential forms as entelechies.*   When these are separated from the things they arise within cognition as inner experience (beholding) through a mutual exchange between the soul and the things. For Goethe, the entelechy was “the power that calls itself from within itself into existence” (GA 1, p.83). In it, the totality conditions, from out of itself and in accordance with its essential being, all the sin- gle, individual parts. This is the system-building principle, the principle of life. It is also the idea of the organism (the type, in the Goethean sense, the entelechy working within the organism). “But the idea of the organism,” says Rudolf Steiner, “is actively at work as entelechy within the organism; in the form in which it is grasped by our reason (Vernunft) it is only the essential being of the entelechy itself. It does not summarize experience; it brings into being what shall be experienced. Goethe expressed this as follows: ‘Concept is a summing-up, idea is a result of experience; summing up requires the power of under- standing (Verstand), to grasp the result, the power of reason is required’ (Sayings in Prose, 17, 2)” (ibid. p.85). To this it should be added that the Scholastics regarded the universals – or essential forms – present in the soul of man “in the things” and “after the things” as one and the same and believed their difference lay only in the character of their manifestation. We “sum up” the primary qualities of things through use of the method of rational empiricism. But this proves to be inadequate when it comes to taking hold of the “essential forms” in which the realm of the living comes to expression. In this case, Goetheanism resorts to the power of judgment in beholding. Of this, one can say the same as Goethe says of the entelechy, namely, that this power calls itself into existence from out of itself. In other words, in beholding, the “things-in-themselves” of the world are revealed to man, its entelechies, which are intelligible beings. In thinking about thinking, through the transformation of his outer into an inner (intuitive) mode of observation, the human being comes into immediate contact with the entelechy; he attains knowledge “in a single flash”.

* The “things-in-themselves” of the world, when they are grasped by human cognition.
_______

The Goethean theory of knowledge orders the hierarchy of the objects of cognition through cognitive methods that belong intrinsically to them. Only right at the summit of their pyramid do subject and object of cognition achieve complete unity. The (in contrast to Locke’s opinion) subjective knowledge of the primary qualities of things merges together with the objective knowledge of the secondary qualities, within the unitary ‘I’ of the human being. Then that which is immanent in subject and object proves to be one.

Rudolf Steiner adopted the standpoint of Goethe. He characterizes the above-mentioned “pyramid of knowledge” as follows: “In the inorganic world it is essential to bear in mind that the phenomenon in its multiplicity is not identical with the lawful system that explains it, but merely points to this, as to something external to it. ‘Die Anschauung’ – the material element of cognition (Anschauung here means ordinary observation – G.A.B.) which is given to us through the outer senses, and the concept – the formal element – through which we recognize the observation as something necessary, stand over against each other as elements that objectively require one another, but in such a way that the concept lies, not within the single members of a sequence of phenomena, but in a relation of these members to one another. This relation, which draws the multiplicity together into a unitary whole, has its basis in the single, individual parts of what is given, but as a wholeness (a unity) it does not come to real, concrete manifestation. Only the members (i.e. the elements of the system – G.A.B.) of this relation come to outer existence – in the object. The unity, the concept only comes to manifestation as such within our understanding faculty (Verstand).... We have here to do with a duality, with the thing in its multiplicity, which we observe, and the unity, which we think.” In organic nature “the unity comes to reality in the observed object, together with the multiplicity, as identical with it. The relation of the single members of a total phenomenon (organism) has become real. It no longer comes to concrete manifestation merely in our understanding faculty, but does so in the object itself, in which it brings forth the manifoldness from within itself. The concept has not merely the role of a sum, a drawing together which has its object outside itself; it has become completely united as one with the object. What we behold is no longer different from that through which we think what is beheld; we behold the concept as idea. This is why Goethe calls the faculty by which we grasp organic nature – anschauende Urteilskraft: the power of judgment in beholding. That which explains – the formal element of cognition, the concept – and that which is explained – the material, observed element – are identical” (GA 1, p.85 ff.).

The concept, when it works with the organic realm, brings forth as result the natural law which governs the percepts. To the power of judgment in beholding is revealed the entelechy, the ‘ur’-phenomenon, the type, the archetypal plant. In them “ideal and real have become a unity” (ibid. p.87). Thus, by virtue of the transition from concept to idea the visible manifoldness of sensory being shows itself to be an ideal unity. For this reason, genuine science can only occupy itself with ideal objects; it can only be idealism, and all empiricism of the world of appearance must be led up to its heights. Nature awakens questions in the human being, and as he finds answers to them he gives birth to higher nature within himself. This, for its own part, asks still higher questions. Thus, “idealism... is nothing other than experience in its entirety, the sum-total of all that it is possible for us to know of things, while that which the empiricists usually make the object of their science is only one half of experience – the items for addition, with no total” (GA 30, p.307). In order to grasp this conclusion of the Anthroposophical doctrine of science (Wissenschaftslehre) and accept it willingly, we must, like Goethe and Hegel, experience to some degree the capacity of our thinking spirit to be the organ of ideal perception.

At the beginning of chapter II we tried, with the help of Fig.7, to express the principle of the world’s becoming, in which the eternal, the most High itself changes its character. We now have the possibility of expressing in diagrammatic form the working of this principle in the human being. This we will do by bringing to completion what is shown in Figs. 55 and 56 (at the beginning of this chapter) and, this time, juxtaposing the two aspects.

As we see from the diagrams, the human being, in leading back again to a unity the wholeness of reality that has been divided for him into concept and percept, truly accomplishes a Divine work which, though it was begun without him, can only be completed with his ac- tive participation. Herein lies the essential nature of cognition as an act of consecration. This needs to be begun with full understanding of the fact that thinking has the same significance for the one and eternal idea as the eye has for colour or the ear for sound. It is the organ for com- prehension-perception. When we think in this way we unite things which, according to customary thinking, are incompatible: “empirical method with idealistic results of research” (GA 1, p.127).

In the final analysis nature, too, is spirit, and in the subjective capacity of man for cognition nature created an organ through which the spirit which has become the higher nature of the human being, can express itself. Rudolf Steiner called the power of judgment in beholding: intellectus archetypus (see Beiträge 10, p.14).

A task that still remains to us is to consider the third of those worlds which constitute the human being: that which is represented in the ‘I’ by memory. This question will be discussed in chapter IX, and in what has emerged in the course of the present chapter we have prepared ourselves for a deeper understanding of the fourth and fifth chapters of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’.


<font face="Helvetica, Arial, sans-serif">G. A. Bondarev - Rudolf Steiner’s ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ As the Foundation of the Logic of Beholding Thinking. Religion of the Thinking Will. Organon of the New Cultural Epoch. Volume 2</font>


Chapter 4 – The World as Percept

As we approach the study of this chapter, the main thing to be borne in mind is that within the structure of the first part of the book it plays the same role as the fourth element within the structure of the thought- cycle. In this chapter the ‘beholding’ type of thinking prevails. Its logical conclusions do not play a decisive part, but merely prepare the ground for what is to come. The development of the thought appeals primarily to certain truths that have become apparent through the previous content. We observe from the very beginning that no extra intellectual effort is required for the reading of this chapter. Such an effort would only disturb our understanding. But all the more are we asked to direct our gaze into our own being, where ‘from the other side’, so to speak, the crux of the matter must become evident to us indirectly – somewhat in the way that discoveries are made.

The content of the chapter can best be united with our soul if we treat it as thought-experience. It must become apparent to us that our thinking is moved forward not so much by the development of ideas as by that deep, half-conscious will-impulse referred to in the Postscript to chapter 3. The will-element is revealed here both in the thinking, which outwardly is weakened to a certain extent, and in the organ of sense with which we are observing. By virtue of the style and character of the chapter it is asked of us for the first time that we should begin consciously to experience the otherwise unconscious nature of the will. Then we will experience the world-metamorphosis – reflected in the conflict of world-views – of the real forms of world-being, from their subjective representation within us in the form of the primary qualities of things, to their objective essential being which is of a purely ideal nature.

The subjective primary qualities of things are products of our understanding faculty. We made use of them when we were studying the first three chapters of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. It was then that the cardinal question arose for us: What are we to do with sensory perceptions, the secondary qualities of things? The answer to this is given in chapters 5, 6 and 7 of the first part of the book. These chapters arise as a profound metamorphosis of the first three chapters, the key point of

which is chapter 4. Its position corresponds to that of the Earth aeon within the evolutionary cycle. The first three chapters are found again, after they have passed through the fourth – or, rather, through the activity of our ‘I’, since it all has to do with the ability of the subject to cancel (aufheben) itself here in the lower ‘I’ and give the higher ‘I’ the possibility of manifesting within it – in the second triad of the thought- cycle of the first Part of the book – in the a posteriori of the activity of ‘I’ that has come into effect. This can be represented as shown in Fig.58.

The content of the whole of part one has, as it were, two dimensions. One of them is the development of the theme, which proceeds continuously from the beginning to the end of Part I (shown in the figure as a dotted line -----); the second is built up symmetrically, and the chapters within it are, so to speak, enclosed inside one another so that, figuratively speaking, their ‘overlay’ is particularly ‘dense’ immediately before and after Cycle IV of chapter 4, and ‘thin’ at the beginning and end of this Part. This structural peculiarity of the text is conditioned by the many-layered nature of the thinking that moves forward according to the laws of seven-membered metamorphosis. At the ‘periphery’ of this Part, so to speak, i.e. at its beginning and its end, it has a more intellectual quality. At the centre, the ‘layers’ of beholding thinking overlie those of intellectual thought.

In correspondence with the character of the structure of Part I, our cognizing spirit must also work – our ‘I’ as the will-centre of transformation. Here the will must be brought into thinking, otherwise we remain caught up in empty intellectual conceptions and cannot find a relation to the book. ‘Intellectual beholding’ weakens the abstract power of thinking, but this requires, all the more, the development of a special inner activity of will, the suppressing of the instinctive sphere of the working of the will in blood-circulation and nervous system, so that the organ of thinking is transformed through the will in the ‘I’ into an organ of ideal perception.

The will character of beholding thinking occurs with the greatest force in element 4, but is also present in elements 2 and 6. This whole triad has a special connection with the ‘I’. But one cannot attain ‘beholding’ if one fails to experience the heightened will-character of the thinking through the book as a whole. This character is even reflected in the quotations contained in it. This has been well understood by Otto Palmer, who says in the book we have already mentioned: “The quotations which one encounters in the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ serve a different purpose (from that in the general run of philosophical writings – G.A.B.), which becomes apparent when one omits the names of the philosophers quoted and brings the thoughts themselves without reference to their authors. The structure of the book is not affected. They serve partly as a resistance through the overcoming of which the strength of thought is enhanced, or which enable a new thought to light up, or they are an obstruction aimed to prevent one’s thinking from launching out in a wrong direction. They fulfill these functions totally, within the limits of the texts as quoted by Rudolf Steiner. For this reason, Rudolf Steiner does not consider it really necessary to discuss contemporary philosophy within the context of this book.... But if the reader lets himself be led and guided by the quotations in the way indicated, he will realize that the chain of thought in this work is not of an abstractly logical nature, but impels him to a thought-dynamic, one might almost say a thought-eurythmy. We have here to do with philosophy as an art of thinking. Whoever works his way into this dynamic of thought must activate his will in the process. Thus arises... will in thinking....”137

In the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’, this thought-will arises, of course, with far greater strength in Rudolf Steiner’s own text than in the quoted passages. But in order to be convinced that this is so, it is not enough just to know about it – it is essential, with the aid of the relevant exercises, to experience what is taking place within the thinking spirit.

The fourth chapter consists of seven clearly and distinctly formed cycles. As, within the structure of the whole first Part of the book it corresponds to the element of ‘beholding’, the main feature of the sev- en-membered thought-cycle, consisting of seven chapters, has its roots in this chapter. It constitutes in a sense the thought-seed of the whole first Part, and, though not in the temporal sequence of the development of thought, grows in both directions: towards the beginning of the first Part and towards the end. And this being so, the beginning and end are to some degree morphologically predetermined by the middle of this section of the book. We will discover something similar in the second Part of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. By virtue of this fact, the principle of symmetry is also rooted in chapter 4; it metamorphoses the first three chapters into the three that follow it. It is able to fulfil this task perfectly and completely, thanks to the fact that it is itself seven-membered, consisting of seven cycles.

The abstract-dialectical tension of thought is weakened in this chapter, as indicated already in its title. Thinking unfolds more like an organic process; the thought grows as though of itself. The thesis of Cycle I is complex. It, too, is structured in a sevenfold way.

    CYCLE I

1.      Through thinking, concepts and ideas arise. ‡ What a concept is, cannot be expressed in words         (1-2.)*
      Words can only draw our attention to the fact that we have concepts. ‡ When someone sees a              (3.)  
      tree, his thinking reacts to his observation; an ideal counterpart is added to the object, and he                (4.)
      regards the object and the ideal counterpart as belonging together. ‡ When the object disappears
      from his field of observation, all that remains behind is its ideal counterpart. ‡ This is the concept of        (5.)
      the object. ‡ The wider our experience grows, the greater the sum of our concepts becomes.                  (6-7.)

* The reader may ask himself the question: wherein lies the contradiction in the “bipolar” element (1-2)? The answer is to be found in sub-element (3) of element 3.
_____

Although what we experience as we read the thesis, only unfolds in thought, it has nevertheless grown before our gaze like a small plant. The antithesis arises in a similar way, though it too is only built up out of the material of concepts. Anything that is striving towards the organic level is inwardly structured. Thus each part of the triad has a structure of its own. As to the synthesis, the sevenfoldnesses of the thesis and antithesis which undergo metamorphosis grow within it to a wider and still higher totality. As a result of this, the dialectical triad of the Cycle proves to have the quality of intellectual beholding. Thus its character, which corresponds to the fourth element of the thought-cycle, is evident from the very beginning of chapter 4.

2.         However, in no way do concepts stand in isolation from one another. ‡ They join together to form      (1-2.)
       a structured whole. ‡ The concept ‘organism’, for example, connects on to others: ‘development in         (3-4.)   
       accordance with law; growth’. ‡ Other concepts which are formed in relation to individual things, are       (5.)
       completely absorbed into a single concept. ‡ All the concepts of the lion that I form for myself are
       absorbed into the conceptual totality ‘lion’.                                                                                                   (6-7.)

3.        In this way, single concepts join together into a closed conceptual system, in which each one              (1.)
       has its own special place. ‡ Ideas are qualitatively no different from concepts. They are, simply,              (2.)
       concepts that are more filled with content, richer and more encompassing. ‡ I would stress that it is
       important to bear in mind here that I have taken as my starting-point
thinking, and not concepts               (3.)
       and
ideas, which are only gained by means of thinking. They presuppose the activity of thinking. ‡
       Consequently, what I have said about the self-contained, completely undetermined nature of thinking       (4.)
       cannot simply be transferred and applied to concepts. (I make explicit mention of this here, as this is
       where I differ with
Hegel, who posits the concept as the primary and original element.)
           ‡ The concept cannot be drawn from observation. ‡ This is evident from the fact that the growing        (5.)(6.)
       human being only slowly and gradually forms the concepts for the objects that surround him. ‡ The
       concepts are added to observation.                                                                                                              (7.)

In a way that is convincing and clear to follow, the content of the triad has led us onto the path of the development of that monism in which the birth of the free motive of activity is possible. But we are still surrounded by the world of one-sidednesses and errors which does not even allow us to tread the path where we would solve the riddle of the nature of thinking, not through abstract logic, but through an analysis of our observations. Beholding comes into contradiction with the dialectical triad of the Cycle. As it happens, the contradiction is resolved in element 5, also through beholding: Spencer’s mistaken observation awakens in us the wish to repeat it – though this time without the mistake – and then our idea appears to us again, but now in the right light. We have already experienced the strongly ‘beholding’ quality of the dialectical triad in the Cycle. In the new, conceptual-beholding triad consisting of elements 3, 4 and 5, the dialectical principle continues to work, but now within the sphere of the logic of beholding in thinking, where thinking stands over against beholding and where it is not the understanding, but ideal perception which plays the dominant role. Thus the abstractness of thinking is overcome step by step.

4.      A widely-read philosopher of the present day (Herbert Spencer) describes in the following way the
     mental (geistig) process which we carry out in relation to observation: “If, when walking through the fields
     some day in September, you hear a rustle a few yards in advance, and on observing the ditch-side where
     it occurs, see the herbage agitated, you will probably turn towards the spot to learn by what this sound and
     motion are produced. As you approach there flutters into the ditch a partridge; on seeing which your curiosity
     is satisfied – you have what you call an explanation of the appearances. The expla- nation, mark, amounts
     to this – that whereas throughout life you have had countless experiences of disturbances among small
     stationary bodies, accompanying the movement of other bodies among them, and have generalized the
     relation between such disturbances and such movements, you find this particular disturbance explained
     on finding it to present an instance of the like relation” (‘First Principles’, Part I, par. 23).

5.       Closer examination obliges us to take a different view of the matter. When I hear a noise, the first thing
     I do is to seek the concept for this observation. Only when I have this concept am I led beyond the noise itself.
     A person who thinks no further simply hears the noise and is quite content with this. But through my thinking I
     realize that I have to look upon the noise as an effect. Thus, only when I connect the concept of
effect with
     the percept of the noise, am I prompted to go beyond the single observation and seek for the
cause.

The process of the individualization of ideas is also made especially clear in this Cycle. Let us compare the end of element 5 with element 6. In both, the theme is the same, but the direction of the thinking process is different: leading in the first case towards the object, and in the second towards the subject. It is only thanks to this fact that the individualizing of the idea takes place: it has united itself with our ‘I’. An insufficiently acute thought-sense may well find these distinctions far too subtle and therefore questionable. It will be significantly easier to feel them and grasp their meaning when we move on to the general and definitive conclusion within the Cycle, which is contained in element 7. We have described its character as a striving towards a higher universality (generality). In this element these distinctions reveal the decisive role they have to play.

6.        The concept of effect calls forth that of cause, and I then seek for the object that acts as the cause, and
      find it in the shape of the partridge. However, I can never find these concepts of cause and effect through
      mere observation, no matter how many cases I extend it to. Observation calls forth thinking, and this alone
      sets me on the path that enables me to connect one experience with another.

7.        If the demand is made of a ‘strictly objective science’ that it should draw its content from observation
      alone, then one should, at the same time, require that it abstain altogether from thinking. For thinking, by
      its very nature, goes beyond what is observed.

Because chapter 4 plays the part of the axis, or one can also say the point of symmetry in the sevenfold structure of the chapters, it is closely connected in its first three Cycles with the first three chapters. This is quite definitely reflected in the transition from chapter 3 to chapter 4. This transition comes to expression with particular clarity thanks to the Postscript to chapter 3. Which is not to say that without the Postscript no transition would exist. It does indeed exist, but for the inexperienced reader it would be (owing to the aphoristic character of the form etc.) considerably more difficult to recognize.

If we take the final, seventh element of the Postscript to chapter 3, and bring it into connection with the first and last elements of Cycle I of chapter 4, we obtain nothing less than a dialectical triad, but one that unfolds in a reverse direction: from the fourth to the third chapter. This means that we have to do here with a kind of ‘counter-movement’ of the content. Such is the complex phenomenology of the organic movement of the spirit (subject) as it thinks according to the method of ‘beholding’.

     Chapter 4, Cycle I
     Element 7: Thinking goes beyond what is observed.
     Element 1: Through thinking, concepts and ideas arise.
    
Postscript to Chapter 3
    
Element 7: If we leave the sphere of thinking, we find nothing that acts as its cause.

As we move on to Cycle II, we should note how sharply the Cycles are separated from each other in chapter 4. After reading one of them, it is impossible not to feel the need for a pause before moving on to the beginning of the next. At first sight, this would appear to offend against the principle of leading the Cycle to an octave. For our own part, we can only say that the laws of beholding remain mysterious for us at present. We realize that, in the transition from Cycle to Cycle in chapter 4, we are shifting our attention from one object of beholding to another. But all the Cycles (there are seven of them) form a unity within the structure of the chapter. Hence, there is an inner connection between them. This exists in our higher ‘I’ to the extent that we succeed in overcoming (aufheben) our lower ‘I’ in the transition from the third to the fourth chapter. We have already mentioned that elements 2, 4 and 6 are important less for their content than for their ability to metamorphose the remaining four elements. All connections between the elements are, essentially, laws of their metamorphoses. And these laws are objective. Elements 2, 4 and 6 work, themselves, as laws of the metamorphoses, but in addition to this they have an entirely subjective character: what brings them into being is the thinking ‘I’. The leading over of the sevenfold ‘musical scale’ – or the Cycle – of thinking to an octave takes place by virtue of the objective law of the movement of thinking. In element 4 (of both the chapter and the Cycle) the law of the subjective movement of the spirit gains the upper hand over the objective law, and the former has, without being untrue to itself, to assume the character of the latter (objective law). Then the conditioning principle in the movement of thought, and its system-forming principle, will raise themselves above the level of otherness-of-being, and ascend into the world of essential being. The law of the negation of the thinking subject calls forth the ascent to beholding. The fourth element (or the fourth stage) itself is the realization in practice of beholding in accordance with the laws of beholding. This is a kind of ‘inverted’ Pralaya at its highest point, reflected within the microcosm, the beginning of its freedom.

The second Cycle in chapter 4 is short and vigorous in its movement. As to content, it is devoted to the theme dealt with in the final (seventh) Cycle of chapter 3. Thus the main antithesis of chapter 4 corresponds to the concluding Cycle of chapter 3. Herein comes to expression once more the orientation of the first half of chapter 4 towards what precedes it, as this has to be metamorphosed by the content of chapter 4 into the last three chapters of the first part of the book. We will now experience Cycle II in its entirety.


CYCLE II

1.-2.        The moment has now come for us to turn from thinking to the thinking being. For this is the agent
          through which thinking is connected with observation. Human consciousness is the place where concept
          and observation meet and where they are brought into connection with one another.

3.             But this is how, at the same time, this (human) consciousness may be characterized. It is the
          mediator between thinking and observation.

4.             To the extent that the human being observes an object, this appears to him as something given;
          to the extent that he thinks, he appears to himself as an active agent. He looks upon the thing observed
          as
object, and upon himself as a thinking subject. Because he directs his thinking to the observation he
          has consciousness of the objects; because he directs his thinking towards himself, he has consciousness
          of himself or Self-Consciousness.

5.              Human consciousness must, of necessity, be self-consciousness at the same time, because it is
          thinking
consciousness. For, when thinking directs its gaze towards its own activity, it has its very own
          essential being, in other words its subject, standing over against itself as an object.

6.              What must not be overlooked, however, is the fact that only with the help of thinking are we able
           to determine ourselves as subject and place ourselves over against the objects. For this reason,
           thinking should never be regarded as a merely subjective activity. Thinking is
beyond subject and
           object. It forms these two concepts just as it does all the others. Thus, when we as thinking subject
           relate the concept to an object, we must not regard this relation as a merely subjective thing. It is not
           the subject which establishes the relation, but thinking. The subject does not think because it is a subject;
           it appears to itself as a subject because it is able to think. The activity exercised by man as a
thinking
          
being is, therefore, not merely subjective; it is an activity that is neither subjective nor objective,
           transcending both of these concepts. I ought never to say that my individual subject thinks; the truth is,
           rather, that the subject owes its existence to thinking.

7.                Hence thinking is an element that leads me beyond myself and unites me with the objects. But at
            the same time it separates me from them by setting me over against them as a subject.
                   This is what accounts for the dual nature of the human being: he thinks, and in so doing
            encompasses himself and the rest of the world; but at the same time he must, by means of thinking,
            determine himself as an individual standing over against the things.

Let us once again compare the content of this Cycle with that of Cycle VII of the third chapter. We discover that in the final, seventh element of Cycle II, which plays the role of antithesis within the chapter, a synthesis takes place of the two juxtaposed and contrasting Cycles. In this case one can experience the following, third Cycle of chapter 4 as a beholding of this synthesis. With regard to content it fits this role perfectly. Thus comes to view the living interweaving in the text of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. In its sequence of chapters, the one grows into the other, all following the overall plan, the organization of the structure. Processes in the development of thought become manifest, the one of which overlies the other, thus showing the multi- functionality of their elements. And seen as a whole, a system of systems, free of contradiction, emerges, similar to the way in which in the universe ‘I’-beings live within the structure of other ‘I’-beings and find in them their highest expression. This is yet another phenomenon of the personalistic organism of thinking inherent in the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. Its trains of thought ‘sprout up’ in accordance with lawful principles which condition the existence not just of the living entity, but also of the thinking being (or the being of thought – Trans.).

In the structure of chapter 4, Cycle III is unquestionably a synthesis, although Rudolf Steiner opens it with the following words: “The next thing we have to do, will be to ask ourselves....” Of decisive importance here, we repeat, is the ‘beholding’ character of the chapter. Its development is driven forward by, not an external, but an internal struggle of its parts. This ‘next’ question is the main question of the chapter: namely, in what relation does the content of our observations stand to our thinking? The question arises as we draw together a series of opposites: thinking and idea, concept and percept, consciousness and thinking, consciousness and observation and, finally, subject and object. Not only as a result of what is said in the first three Cycles of chapter IV, but also thanks to the series of discussions that precede it, we are led to sense inwardly in our thinking that what is common to all these pairs of opposites is that in each case the constituent elements come towards us as observations.

             CYCLE III

1.           The next thing we have to do, will be to ask ourselves: How does that other element which, so far,
        we have simply referred to as the object of observation and which comes to meet thinking within our
        consciousness – how does it enter this consciousness?

2.            To answer this question, we must remove from our field of consciousness all that has already been
         brought into it by way of thinking. Because the content of our consciousness at any given time is
         invariably pervaded already with concepts in the most varied ways.
               We must picture to ourselves that a being with fully developed human intelligence springs forth from
         nowhere and suddenly has the world in front of him. All that he becomes aware of before he activates his
         thinking –
that is the pure content of observation. The world would then only show to this being the
         disconnected aggregate of
objects of sensation: colours, sounds, sensations of pressure, warmth, taste
         and smell; then feelings of pleasure and pain.

3.              This aggregate is the content of pure, thought-free observation. Standing over against it is thinking,
         which is ready to set in motion its activity as soon as it finds something to connect onto. Experience
         shows that it is soon found. Thinking is able to draw connecting threads from one element of
         observation to another. It unites certain concepts with these elements, thereby drawing them into a
         relation with one another.

As object of beholding in this third Cycle, element 5 from Cycle I is taken, in which the author gives expression to his own opinion. This is the first such case we have met in the book – where the positive results attained by the author are made an object of beholding. What follows from the beholding stands in an immediate relation to element 6 in Cycle II. Thus the development of the ideas in the book assumes the features of an independence of being above and beyond their connection with the ideas of the surrounding world.

4.                We already saw above how a noise that we encounter is brought into relation with another
           observation through the fact that we characterize the first as an effect of the second.

5.                 If we now recall that the activity of thinking can in no way be regarded as subjective, we will
           not be tempted to imagine that the kind of connections that thinking brings about only have subjective
           validity.

The sixth element in Cycle III presents us with an individual task, the fulfilment of which takes us to the end of the chapter, and even beyond. This can give us an inkling of the fact that with Cycle III an important stage in our research reaches its conclusion and we must brace ourselves for a new task. Thus individualization and the result of Cycle III merge into one. But as the result is the all-unity (in the Cycle) which has special significance for the further stages of the discussion, the need arises to construct element 7 in such a way that it serves as a transition from Cycle III to Cycle IV, even to what will follow right up to the end of the chapter. This task is assumed by element [7].

6-7.               Our task will now be to seek, through thoughtful observation, the relation which the immediate
            datum of observation given above has to our conscious subject.

[7.]                 In view of the shifting nature of linguistic usage it seems to me necessary to come to an
            agreement with the reader on the meaning of a word that I have to use in the discussion that follows.
            I will be calling the immediate objects of sensation enumerated above, to the extent that the conscious
            subject becomes aware of them through observation: perceptions. Thus it is not the process of
            observation, but the
object of this observation that I refer to with the term. [Translator’s note: the less
            ambiguous word ‘percept’ will mostly be used here.] I prefer not to use the expression
‘sensation’,
            because this has a special meaning in physiology, narrower than that of my concept of perception
            (percept). A feeling I experience within me can certainly be described as a percept, but not as a
            sensation in the physiological sense. For in the case of my feeling, too, I become acquainted with it
            through its becoming a
percept for me. And the way in which we become acquainted, via observation,
            with our thinking is such that we can also call our thinking, in the form in which it first appears to our
            consciousness, percept.

In view of the fact that the principle of perception in the individual thinking spirit is virtually the main subject of our investigations, a many-sided approach will be needed in the attempt to gain an under- standing of it. Here we must give special emphasis to the fact that our consciousness, insofar as it is awake, has to do with two objects: thinking and percept. And both of these are given to perception, albeit in different ways. For this reason, if one wishes to gain insight into the origin of thinking, one must have a corresponding grasp of the character of external perception. This is exactly what Rudolf Steiner does. In what appears, at first sight, to be a quite uncomplicated way he summarizes the content of the first three chapters, ‘prepares’ them in a particular way in the first three Cycles of chapter 4, and now they are ready to begin that process of transformation which leads them from the formal- logical element to that of beholding in thinking. The observable comes into its own.

* * *

It is now essential for us to make a pause in our practical work with the text of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ and look once again at the role of chapter 4 within the structure of the entire first Part of the book. With its seven Cycles this chapter metamorphoses the first three chapters into the last three. In this sense it reveals to us with its structure and content the mystery of the working of the law of metamorphosis. Through experiencing within the chapter the Cycles as elements, we learn to experience chapters as elements in their greater metamorphosis, which contains within itself the ‘knowledge of freedom’. The over- all structure of the chapter in connection with that of Part I of the book can be viewed as we have represented it in Fig.59.

The fourth Cycle of chapter 4 is a kind of “watershed” between the first and second halves of the first Part of the book. On the side that lies before the cycle there are the chapters in which the speculative (dialectical) predominates, bound up as to content and structure with the first three Cycles of chapter 4, which lead them over into what can be ‘beheld’. This takes place in two stages. In the initial stage, the first three Cycles of chapter 4 metamorphose into its last three Cycles, thus giving rise to the possibility of beholding, and then everything changes once more, whereby it remains an interconnected whole, and appears again in chapters 5, 6 and 7. Thus we see that the greater metamorphosis encompassing all seven chapters is inwardly structured with the help of three chains of metamorphoses, which are, so to speak, tied together by a single nodal point (Table 5). There stands behind this configuration, determining the law of its structure, the particular quality of the Earthly aeon.

In order to demonstrate the reality of the chains of structural connections which we have discovered and represented in a tabular form, it would be helpful to analyze their content, but for reasons of space we cannot do this. We will, however, at least consider the first, and touch upon the other two only briefly.

In our fourth chapter (see note p.9), where we presented an over- view of the relevant literature, we mentioned that F. Teichmann made an attempt in his book to trace the structure of the first part of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. He suggests that one should divide chapter 3 into seven parts and see in each of these the reflection of a chapter. But as this intention is lacking in any methodological basis*,  it remains for us nothing more than a thought-game. If one wishes to use the method involving numbers, then this presupposes that one knows the laws according to which “God mathematizes” when He creates organic wholes. In the case of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ the law of mirror-reflection is closely bound up with the law of symmetry and with the laws of seven-membered metamorphosis. These work together in a unity. If this is unknown to us then the organic wholeness of the book remains beyond our grasp. Once we recognize this, however, it illumines for us the structure of the seven chapters in the way shown in Table. 5. Here one can also use a geometrical picture. We then arrive at three mutually overlapping circles (or three spheres), recalling the relation of the three bodies of the human being: physical, etheric and astral bodies (Fig.60).

* To provide it with one is impossible, for the simple reason that the initial idea is entirely far-fetched.

_____

The fourth Cycle of chapter 4 constitutes the centre of the whole of Part I of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. It is, so to speak, the seed from which this Part grows, and it does so from the centre to the periphery, towards both its end and its beginning. We therefore unlock a further mystery of the book when we experience the middle Cycle of its fourth chapter as the book’s true beginning: as the beginning for ‘beholding’ thinking, of course; for ‘knowledge at one stroke’. For conceptual thinking the book begins with the first chapter. It grows out of humanity’s entire experience of thinking and of life hitherto. But as a new creation – with respect to the quality of thinking – the book can only grow from out of itself and afterwards enter into contact with the old world. The question with which chapter 1 begins is actually the ‘periphery’ of the book, where it takes up contact with what is, from its own stand- point, the external world of science, with its results, its views on the question of freedom. Is the human being free in his thought and action? This problem is familiar not only to philosophers, but to the majority of educated people. But we repeat: On the level of abstract thinking the first page of the book is its beginning. It is also characteristic of conceptual thinking to begin with the statement of a generally-known fact. Rudolf Steiner does not depart from this rule, but he does not wish, in conceding to intellectualism, to be untrue to himself. Let us recall what is written on the title-page of the book: “The Results of Soul-Observation according to the Scientific Method”. A book in which ab- solutely everything is concrete and interconnected and in which the formal element is entirely absent, begins, organically speaking, where the living centre of symmetry (the seed) is to be found within it. And this is Cycle IV of chapter 4.

We must take two facts into account. Thinking consciousness is the final product of the period of the evolutionary cycle which has come to an end, and this cycle is subject to the law of symmetry. Symmetry of forms, of spatial relations, is only one of the expressions of this universal law. The symmetry of the entire evolutionary cycle is the highest ‘ur’-phenomenon for all its inner states and manifestations. Now an ‘ur’-phenomenon is always dynamic; through the symmetry of thinking a qualitatively new manifestation of the ‘ur’-phenomenon is brought about. The human being starts off by grasping through his understanding as he does with his faculty of sight: spatially, from the centre to the periphery. What is characteristic of the ‘power of judgment in beholding’ is that the one who possesses it experiences, even in conceptual thinking, comprehension of the object in its complete fullness and ‘at one stroke’. As a book for inner exercise, the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ teaches us, through the working of its structure, how we can acquire this capacity by dint of practice. Thus we learn in the first chain of connections (see Table 5) to experience the ‘outermost circle’ of the first Part, through which it enters into contact with the surrounding historical-philosophical and scientific world – i.e. with the world around it. As it receives into itself this surrounding world, it moves, in its solution of the question of freedom, towards its own centre. This ‘circle’ of thinking is the most spiritual, but only on an abstract level. One can compare it with the astral body of the human being. In the stage that follows, the circle of the second chain is superimposed upon this bigger circle (see Fig.60) and that of the third upon these two.

Such is the movement of dialectical ‘beholding’ thinking. Another travels in the opposite direction – from the centre to the periphery. In order to experience in this way the cycle of the seven chapters, one must of course read the book in the usual way from beginning to end. After that, one can try to think through each of the parts, moving from the centre in both directions – towards the beginning and the end. But before we carry out such an experiment, we must examine the remaining Cycles of chapter 4.

If one tries to think, not in a linear manner, but ‘spherically’, so to speak, one can really experience the thought-form at the centre of Cycle IV as the beginning of the book. Let us read the Cycle as a whole.

              CYCLE IV

1.           The naïve human being regards the data of his perception, on the level on which they appear to him
         directly, as things that have an existence entirely independent of himself. When he sees a tree he believes
         initially that it is standing, with the shape that he sees, with the colours of its various parts, there at the spot
         towards which his gaze is directed. When the same person sees, in the morning, the sun appearing as a
         disc on the horizon, and follows the movement of this disc, he is quite sure that all this exists (in itself) in
         this form and proceeds in just the way he observes it.

2.            He holds firmly to this belief until he has other perceptions which contradict the earlier ones. The child,
         before it has any experience of distance, reaches out to touch the moon, and only corrects what at first
         glance it had held to be real, when a second perception comes into contradiction with the first.

3.            Whenever a widening of the circle of my perceptions takes place, I am obliged to correct my picture
         of the world. This is true in everyday life just as it is in the spiritual development of humanity.

4.            The picture which the ancients had of the relation of the earth to the sun and the other heavenly bodies
         had to be replaced with a different one by Copernicus because it conflicted with previously unknown
         perceptions. When Dr. Franz operated on someone who had been born blind, the latter said that before
         his operation he had formed, on the basis of the perceptions arising through his sense of touch, a quite
         different picture of the size of objects. He had to correct the perceptions arising from his sense of touch by
         means of those gained through vision.

5.             How is it that we are continually forced to correct our observations?

6.             A simple reflection brings us the answer to this question. When I am standing at one end of a
         tree-lined boulevard, the trees far from me at the other end appear smaller and closer together than the
         ones where I am standing. The picture I perceive becomes different when I change the place from which
         I make my observations. Thus the form in which it presents itself to me is determined by a factor that has
         to do, not with the object, but with myself as the observer. For a row of trees the place where I happen to
         be standing is a matter of complete indifference. But the picture I receive of it depends crucially upon this
         factor. Similarly, it is a matter of indifference to the sun and the plane- tary system that human beings
         observe them from the earth. But the perceptual image presented to us is determined by the place where
         we live in the cosmos. This dependency of the perceptual image upon the point of observation is the one
         that we can most easily grasp. The matter becomes more difficult when we come to recognize the
         dependency of our world of perception upon our physical and mental organization. The physicist shows
         us that, within the space in which we hear a sound, air-vibrations are occurring, and that the spatial body
         in which we seek the origin of the sound is also subject to a vibratory movement of its parts. We only
         perceive this movement as sound if we have a normally-organized ear. Were we not to have such an ear,
         the whole world would remain for us eternally silent. Physiology tells us that there are people who perceive
         nothing of the wonderful display of colours all around us. The picture given to their perception only has
         shades of light and dark. There are others who do not perceive one particular colour, for example red.
         Their image of the world is lacking in this colour, and therefore differs from that of the average person.

7.              I would like to call the dependency of my perceptual image upon my place of observation ‘mathematical’,
          and that upon my organization ‘qualitative’. The former determines the relative sizes of my percepts and
          the distances between them, and the latter determines their quality. The fact that a red surface appears
          to me red – this determination of quality – depends upon the organization of my eye.

Let us now recall the beginning of chapter 1, where the question was raised whether the human being is free in his thought and action. This was indeed the ‘periphery’ (the ‘displacement’ of the centre) in the sense that this question can only arise as a result of great effort in the realm of thought and observation. It is therefore easy to arrive at the conclusion at the beginning of chapter 1 that this question is the most important of all in science, religion and life itself. But what we have in the middle of chapter 4 is, in fact, the first emergence of this question. For here everything takes its start from the naïve human being, who has had his first experience of the perceived world. The discussion here recalls another, that of Condillac in his analysis of perceptions, where he takes a statue and endows it with one sensory faculty after another.

The Cycle concludes with a re-adaptation of the Lockean concepts of primary and secondary qualities, which corresponds to the central core of the question regarding observation. Primary qualities in the broader sense of the word are determined by the ‘place of observation’, above all by the ‘place’ (or standpoint) of the understanding faculty. Secondary qualities appeal to the rest of the human organization. The conclusion to which we are heading at the end of the Cycle, namely that “my perceptual images... are, to begin with, subjective”, corresponds to the path followed by human thought from Locke and Condillac to Kant and Schopenhauer, whereby it constructed the theory of the two worlds and tried in vain to overcome it. Rudolf Steiner brings this question into sharp relief in its essential nature – in relation to human freedom.

The entire structure of the thinking in the first Part of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ can be compared to the circle used by us earlier when we were attempting to understand the general character of world-evolution (see Figs. 23, 24 and 36). It is, indeed, the ‘ur’- phenomenon of thinking consciousness in its genesis from sensory to ideal perception. The human being as a microcosm begins his path to consciousness with the naïve perceptions, and its first stage concludes with the naïve belief of the philosopher that perceptual images are subjective. How one traverses this stage is shown in Cycle V. While we are studying this it is important not to lose sight of the whole: namely, the sphere. The sense-perceptions form its centre and pure thinking its periphery. In order to arrive at the latter it is necessary to carry out a correct analysis of perceptions and finally arrive at the conviction that thinking can also be an object of perception. With this result one should – though now as a being who is already to a certain extent free – return to the centre and perceive there something that is in the highest degree individualizing and supersensible: namely, the conceptual and moral intuitions, which will be discussed in Part II of the book. In Cycle V Rudolf Steiner forms the dialectical triad in a mode of pure beholding and in such a way that its content is traditional, with a mistake inherent in it. In this way it is suggested to us that we should, right from the beginning, enter into active opposition to ourselves if we have already accepted the conclusion of the preceding section implying that we must experience ourselves as naïve realists who are lacking in the ability to attain freedom. We can maintain this opposition all the more easily, the more strongly we have experienced the unspoken meaning of Cycle IV, which awakens doubt as to the truth of its content. Here we are helped by all that has been discussed previously. We have advanced to its centre, having started out from the periphery, and now we are returning to the periphery again.

Thus Cycle V is the beginning of active resistance to the naïve experience of the world of perception; our attention is thereby “shifted away from the object of perception to its subject”. These words appear in element 3 of Cycle V. Let us approach this step by step.

         CYCLE V

1.           In the first instance, therefore, my perceptual images are subjective. ‡ Knowledge of the               (1.)
        subjective character of our percepts can easily lead to doubt as to whether they have any                   (2.)
        objective basis at all. ‡ When we know that a percept, for example that of the colour red or a              (3.)
        certain musical tone, is not possible without a given structure of our organism, we can be tempted
        to believe that this percept, taken in isolation from our subjective organism, ceases to be; that
        without the act of perceiving, whose object it is, it has no existence whatever. This view found a
        classical representative in George Berkeley, who was convinced that from the moment we have
        become aware of the significance of the human subject for perception, we can no longer believe
        in the existence of a world without the conscious mind (Geist).
             ‡ He says: “Some truths there are so near and obvious to the mind that man need only open            (4.)
        his eyes to see them. Such I take this important one to be, viz., that all the choir of heaven and the
        furniture of the earth – in a word, all those bodies which compose the mighty frame of the world –
        have not any subsistence without a mind; that their being consists in their being perceived or known;
        that consequently, so long as they are not actually perceived by me, or do not exist in my mind or
        that of any other created spirit, they must either have no existence at all or else subsist in the mind
        of some Eternal Spirit” (‘Of the Principles of Human Knowledge’, Part 1 Sect. 6). ‡ For this view of
        things there is nothing left of the percept, considered apart from its being perceived. There is no            (5.)
        colour if it is not seen, no sound if it is not heard. Just as little as colour and sound, do extension,
        form and movement exist outside the act of perception. Nowhere do we see extension or form by
        themselves; they are always connected with colour or other quali- ties that are unquestionably
        dependent on our subjectivity. If these disappear with our act of perception, the same must also be
        true of the former, which are bound up with them.

(2.)           The objection can be made that, even if shape, colour, sound have no other existence than that       (6.)
         within the act of perception, there must all the same be things that are there without consciousness
(1.)   and to which our conscious perceptual images bear a resemblance. ‡ The view we have characterized
         counters this objection by saying: a colour can only resemble a colour and a shape can only resemble
         a shape. Our percepts can only resemble our percepts, and nothing else. Even what we call an object is 
         nothing but a group of percepts connected together in a certain way. If I take away from a table: shape,
         extension, colour etc., in other words everything that is only my percept, then nothing is left. ‡ Carried      (7.)
         to its logical conclusion, this view leads to the assertion: The objects of my perception only exist through
         me, and only insofar and so long as I perceive them; they disappear with perception and have no meaning 
         without it. Apart from my percepts, however, I know of no objects and can have no knowledge of them.

2.              No objection can be made to this assertion so long as I merely take into account the general fact
         that the organization of my subject plays a part in determining the quality of my percept. The situation
         would be entirely different if we were able to state what the function of our perception is in the emergence
         of a percept. We would then know what happens to the percept during the act of perception and would
         also be able to determine what must be there before it is perceived.

3.              Our attention is thereby led from the object of perception to its subject.

Now that we have found the most precious and important element, so to speak, around which the entire content of the book revolves – the subject, the human being as a self, the ‘I’ – the element of beholding in the Cycle and that which we then ideally perceive, the final outcome of the Cycle, rests throughout on the basis of the ‘I’-phenomenon.

4.              I do not only perceive other things; I also perceive myself. In the first place, the content of my
         self-perception is that I am the enduring element over against the perceptual images, which are continually
         appearing and disappearing. The percept of my ‘I’ can arise in my consciousness at any time, while I am
         having other perceptions. When I am absorbed in the perception of a given object, initially I only have  
         consciousness of this. The perception of my own self can then arise in addition, with the consequence
         that I am now aware not only of the object but also of my personality, standing over against the object
         and observing it. I do not merely see a tree; I also know that
it is I who am seeing it. I also recognize
         that something is happening in me while I am observing the tree. When the tree disappears from my
         field of vision, a trace of this process remains behind for my consciousness: namely, an image of the tree.
         This image has united itself with my being during the act of observation. An enrichment of my Self has
         taken place; its content has absorbed into itself a new element.

5.              I can call this element my inner representation (mental picture) of the tree. I would never come into
         the position of speaking of
represen- tations if I did not experience these within the percept of my Self.
         Percepts would come and go; I would simply let them pass by.

6.              Only through the fact that I perceive my Self and notice that, with every percept, its content also
         changes, do I feel compelled to bring the observation of the object into connection with the change in
         my own state, and to speak of my inner representation.

                  I perceive an inner representation when I observe myself, in the same way that I perceive colour,
         sound etc. when I direct my attention to other objects.

7.               I can now make the further distinction that I call these other objects, which stand over against me,
         the
outer world, while the content of my self-observation I describe as my inner world.

Thus, in a seemingly modest and inconspicuous way, the most important element in the book has emerged – namely, the ‘I’. This is the mediator (the basis for the relationship) between what is in terms of the genesis of consciousness the perceptual centre, and the ‘circumference’ of thinking. The relation between them is to a lesser degree dialectical and to a higher degree ontological. Here, the ‘I’, the subject, confronts the percept, the object, without knowing how it is to be understood: as a part of the ‘I’ itself, or as a ‘thing-in-itself’? On the other hand, abstract thinking robs the ‘I’ of its substance. In order to come to terms with this situation, the ‘I’, after it has become active in the form of pure actuality, reasserts its sovereignty, which was thrown into question by the activity of perception and thinking. This problem will be dealt with more appropriately in Cycle VI, where the content of Cycle V is individualized, but on this occasion Cycle VI is given a quite special ‘beholding’ quality. It is for the first time that the ‘I’ presents itself so forcibly with the task of ‘dying and becoming’.

In the preceding Cycle the naïve realism of perception was ‘drowned’, and at the same time we became aware of this, so to speak, in the naïve solipsism of Berkeley. Now, in Cycle VI, this becomes the thesis. The standpoint of Kant and other agnostics emerges as the an- tithesis to this. The whole Cycle ends with the collapse of the subjectiv- ity of percepts (Bondarev’s text says ‘representations’), which is put forward by them as an “obvious” truth.

CYCLE VI

1.            Failure to grasp the relation between inner representation and object has led to the greatest
        misunderstandings in modern philosophy. Perception of a change occurring in us, the modification which
        my own self undergoes, has been pushed into the foreground and the object that causes this modification
        has been lost sight of completely. The assertion has been: we perceive, not the objects, but only our inner 
        representations. I know nothing, so it is claimed, of the table in itself which is the object of my observation;
        I know only of the change that happens to me while I perceive the table. This opinion should not be
        confused with that of Berkeley, which we mentioned previously. Berkeley asserts the subjective nature
        of my content of perceptions, but he does not say that I can only know of my inner representations. He
        restricts my knowledge to my inner representations because he believes that there are no objects outside
        the act of inner representa- tion. What I see as a table is, in the view of Berkeley, no longer there from the 
        moment I cease directing my gaze to it. Therefore Berkeley causes my percepts to arise directly through the
        power of God. I see a table, because God calls forth this percept in me. Berkeley therefore knows no other
        real beings (or entities) than God and human spirits. What we call ‘world’ only exists within spirits. What
        the naïve human being calls outer world, bodily nature, does not exist for Berkeley.

2.             Over against this stands the now prevalent Kantian view, which restricts our knowledge of the world
         to our inner representations, not out of a conviction that things cannot exist outside these representations,
         but because it believes that we are so organized that we can only have knowledge of the changes
         undergone by our own Self, and not of the things-in-themselves which cause these changes. It concludes
         from the fact that I only know my inner representations, not that there is no existence independent of these  
         representations, but only that the human subject cannot receive such an existence into itself directly, and
         is able only through “the medium of its subjective thoughts to imagine or invent it, to think, cognize or
         perhaps fail to cognize it” (Otto Liebmann – ‘Analysis of Reality’, p.28). This view of things claims to be
         saying something that is absolutely true and can be seen to be so directly and without proof. “The first
         fundamental principle which the philosopher needs to bring to full clarity of consciousness consists in the
         recognition that our knowledge extends, in the first place, no further than our inner representations. Our inner
         representations are the only thing of which we have direct knowledge, immediate experience; and the
         fact that we experience them directly means that not even the most radical doubt is able to wrest from
         us our knowledge of them. By contrast, the knowledge that extends beyond our inner representation –
         taking this expression here in the broadest sense throughout, to embrace all occurrences of a psychic
         nature – is not immune to doubt. It is therefore necessary at the beginning of philosophizing to state
         explicitly that all knowledge that extends beyond our inner representations is subject to doubt.” Thus
         Volkelt begins his book on ‘Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge’.

3.               However, what is presented here as an immediate and obvious truth is, in reality, the outcome of a
         thought operation which runs as follows:

It is pointless to carry a philosophical discussion of this kind any further, as evidence of another sort has appeared – the evidence of the intellectus archetypus. It is simply necessary here to start again from the very beginning – with what the naïve human being has; then the standpoint of critical idealism must be looked at, and set over against the findings of the physiology of perception. Thus is constituted the central act of beholding in Part I of the book. But why here, in the sixth Cycle? – so one might ask. We must seek the answer in the motto on the book’s title page: “Results of soul observation...” This does not mean the soul observations carried out by the intellect in psychology. “Soul... results” are the fruit of thinking in beholding, of precisely this. And as such it attains its individualization in every sixth element, be it in that of the Cycle, the Cycle series or the chapters. This needs to be grasped once and for all when one is working with the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. In this work, the individual soul observes the higher ‘I’ within the soul, as the higher ‘I’ reaches out to ideal perception of the ideas. This is an absolutely new method and way of thinking, and there is a great risk that this simply goes unnoticed, since the new can only be observed with effort. If this happens, work with the book will be entirely fruitless.

4.             The naïve human being believes that objects, just as he perceives them, also exist outside his
         consciousness. Physics, physiology and psychology, however, seem to suggest that, for perception to take
         place, our organization is necessary, and that we can therefore know nothing of things apart from what is
         transmitted from them by our organization. Hence, our percepts are modifications of our organization,
         and not things-in-themselves. The line of reasoning indicated here has, indeed, been characterized by
         Eduard von Hartmann as the one which must lead to acceptance of the axiom that we can only have direct
         knowledge of our inner representations (see Hartmann’s ‘Basic Problem of Theory of Knowledge’, p.16-40).
         Because we find outside our organism vibrations of bodies and of air, which come towards us as sound-
         impressions, it is argued that what we call sound is nothing but a subjective reaction of our organism to
         those movements in the outer world. In the same way we discover that colour and warmth are only 
         modifications of our organism. It is held that these two kinds of percept are called forth in us through the
         working of processes in the outer world which are entirely different from the experience we have of warmth
         or colour. When such processes excite the nerves of the skin on my body, I have the subjective perception
         of warmth, when they affect the optic nerve, I perceive light and colour. Light, colour and warmth are,
         therefore, the way in which the nerves of my senseorgans respond to the stimulus coming from outside.
         My sense of touch, also, does not transmit to me the objects of the outer world, but only my own states.
         Viewing them in accordance with modern physics, one could imagine that bodies consist of infinitely
         small parts, known as molecules, and that these molecules are not immediately adjacent to one another,
         but have certain distances separating them. Thus there is empty space between them. Across this space
         they work upon one another by means of forces of attraction and repulsion. When I draw my hand close to a
         body, the molecules of my hand do not directly touch those of the body at all; a certain distance remains
         between the body and my hand, and what I experience as the resistance of the body is nothing other
         than the effect of the force of repulsion exerted by its molecules in relation to my hand. I am completely
         outside the body in question and experience only its effect upon my organism. As an extension of this idea
         there is the doctrine of what is known as the specific sense-energies, put forward by J. Müller (1801- 1858).
         It asserts that each sense-organ has the peculiar characteristic of reacting in one special way only, to all
         external stimuli. If a stimulus is directed to my optic nerve, a perception of light occurs, regardless
         whether the effect is produced by what we call light, or whether the nerve is being affected by mechanical 
         pressure or electrical cur- rent. Conversely, different percepts are aroused in different senses, by the same
         outer stimuli. From this it would appear that our senses can only convey what is going on within them, and
         nothing from the outer world. The percepts are determined according to the nature of our senses. Physiology
         shows that there is also no question of our having direct knowledge of the effects produced in our sense-
         organs by the objects. When he investigates the processes in our body, the physiologist finds that already
         in the sense-organs the effects produced by the outer movements are changed in the most varied ways.
         We see this most clearly in the case of the eye and the ear, both of which are highly complex organs which
         fundamentally change the outer stimulus before they convey it to the nerve in question. From the peripheral
         nerve-ending the already changed stimulus is transmitted further to the brain. And here a further stimulus
         must take place, affecting the central organ. It is concluded from this, that the outer process has undergone
         a series of transformations before it enters consciousness. What takes place within the brain is connected
         to the outer process by way of so many intermediary processes, that any similarity to it is completely out of
         the question. All that is finally transmitted by the brain to the human psyche (Seele) is neither outer
         processes, nor processes within the sense-organs, but only those inside the brain. But not even these
         are perceived directly by our inner being (Seele). What we finally have in our consciousness is not brain-
         processes, but
sensations. My sensation of red bears no similarity to the process taking place in the brain
         when I am experiencing the colour red. This, too, arises in our psychic being (Seele) as yet another effect,
         and is merely the result of the brain process. Thus Hartmann says (‘Grundproblem der Erkenntnistheorie’,
         3. 37): “What the subject perceives is there- fore, invariably, modifications of his own psychic states, and
         nothing else.” However, when I have the sensations, they are in no way constituted, as yet, to the
         structured objects of my perceptions. Only single sensations can be transmitted to me by my brain.
         Sensations of ‘hard’ and ‘soft’ can only be conveyed to me by the sense of touch; those of colour and
         light only by the sense of sight. Nevertheless, we find these qualities joined together in one and the same
         object. This union must therefore be brought about by our psychic nature (Seele) itself. That is to say, the
         psyche (Seele) brings together the various sensations transmitted by the brain and forms spatial bodies
         out of them. My brain conveys to me the single sensations of sight, touch and hearing by quite distinct
         paths, and the psyche (Seele) joins them together to form the inner representation ‘trumpet’. This final
         stage (inner representation of the trumpet) of a process is the very first element that is given to my
         consciousness. Nothing of what exists outside me and made the original impression on my senses, can
         be found in it any longer. The external object has become completely lost on the way to the brain and via
         the brain to the human psyche (Seele).

At the threshold to the supersensible, modern humanity experiences – as we have mentioned – a fiasco, falls into a state of crisis. Element 4 has shown us the reason for this, and the latter need only be made conscious. The Greeks had a tradition according to which: If the Temple of Serapis is destroyed, heaven will fall down on the earth; ‘heaven’ referring to the age-old spiritual life. In the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ the ‘temple’ and also the ‘heaven’ of the agnosticism that is sustained by neo-Kantianism and positivism collapses before our very eyes. This collapse is a true blessing, since the ‘temple’ in its fall buries under it the non-freedom of the human being, and new heavens are opened up, whose blue – in the words of Goethe – is already theory. Let us now see what has hitherto obstructed our view of it.

5.             It will be difficult to find in the history of human spiritual-cultural life an edifice of thought that has been
        assembled with greater ingenuity, but which, on closer examination, collapses into nothing.

6.             Let us see how it comes about. We start out from what is given to naïve consciousness, namely, the
        object we perceive. Then the fact is pointed out, that every attribute of this thing would not be there for us
        if we had no sense-organs. No eye – no colour. Colour is therefore not present in what works upon the eye.
        It arises only through the interaction of the eye with the object. Hence the latter is colourless. But the
        colour is also not present in the eye, as a chemical or physical process is taking place there, which has first
        to be conducted by the nerve to the brain, where it gives rise to another process. This is still not the colour,
        which only arises in our psychic nature (Seele) by way of the brain process. Here, it still does not enter my
        consciousness, but is first projected outwards by our psyche onto a spatial body. It is here, finally, that I
        believe I see the colour. We have gone full circle. We became conscious of a coloured object. This is how
        we started out. Now the thought-operation begins. If I had no eyes, the object would be colourless for me. I
        can therefore not locate the colour in the object. I set off in search of it. I look for it in the eye: in vain; in the
        nerve: in vain; in the brain: it is not here, either; in the psyche: yes, I find it here, but not attached to the spatial
        object. I only find the coloured object again, at the place where I started. The circle is closed. I firmly believe
        that what the naïve person thinks is outside him in space is now known to be a product of my own psyche
        (Seele).

7.               So long as we leave it at that, everything seems to be perfectly in order. But we need to go right
         back to the beginning again. Up to now I have been dealing with a thing – with the outer percept, of which
         I formerly had, as a naïve person, an entirely wrong opinion: namely, that it had objective existence in
         precisely the form in which I perceive it. Now I realize that it disappears with my activity of inner picturing
         (Vorstellen), and that it is no more than a modification of my psychic states. Do I now have the right to start
         out from it in my inquiry? Can I say of it that it works upon my psyche (Seele)? I must from now on treat
         the table which, so I previously thought, has an effect upon me and brings about within me an inner
         representation of itself, as being, itself, an inner representation. But then it would follow from this, that my
         sense-organs and the processes occurring in them are also merely subjective. I have no right to speak of
         a real eye, but only of my inner representation of the eye. The same would apply to the nerve paths and the
         brain process, and no less to the process within the psyche itself, through which, out of the chaos of manifold
         sensations, things must be constructed. If, on the assumption of the correctness of the first circular train of
         thought, I think through once more the various parts of my cognitive act, the latter shows itself to be a
         network of inner representations which, as such, cannot possibly work upon one another. I cannot say: My
         inner representation of the object works upon my inner representation of the eye, and there arises out of this
         interaction the inner representation of a colour. But to do so is not necessary in the first place. For, once I
         have clearly recognized that my sense-organs and their activity, my nerve and psychic processes can also
         be given to me only through perception, the train of thought described is shown up in its full absurdity. It is  
         entirely correct to say: for me no percept is given without the corresponding sense-organ. But it is equally
         true to say that there is no sense-organ without a percept of it. I can shift my attention from my percept of
         the table to the eye that sees it, to the epidermal nerves that feel it; but what is going on in these, I can
         again only experience by way of perception. And I soon realize that in the process taking place in the eye
         there is no similarity whatever to that which I perceive as colour. I cannot blot out my percepts of colour by
         pointing out the process taking place in the eye during this act of perception. Just as little do I find the colour
         in the nerve and brain processes; I merely connect new percepts from within my organism with the first,
         which the naïve person locates outside his organism. I merely pass from one percept to another.
                 In addition, there is a hiatus in the whole chain of reasoning. I am able to follow the processes within
         my organism right through to the processes in the brain, even if my suppositions grow more hypothetical,
         the closer I come to the central processes within the brain. The path of external observation comes to an
         end with the process in my brain – with that process, namely, which I would perceive if I could examine the
         brain with the instruments and methods of physics and chemistry. The path of inner observation begins with
         the sensation and extends to the building up of things out of the material of sensation. In the transition from
         the brain-process to sensation the path of observation is interrupted.

In Cycle VII we reach the periphery of the ‘circle’ that embraces the thought-form contained in chapter 4 (see Fig 61), or the beginning of the philosophical reflection whose line of argument in the question of the nature of percepts culminated in the positions of critical idealism and naïve realism. There is no doubt that, as we read on, we arrive at Cycle VII as the outcome of the foregoing development of thinking and beholding. But we notice here a higher degree of abstractness, a style that differs from that of the other Cycles. It can be experienced in this Cycle that, through it, the beholding which is dominant throughout the entire chapter is summed up and, at the same time, the beginning is postulated of the new discussion that awaits us in the following (the 5th) chapter.

The seventh Cycle corresponds fully to its role and its place within the structure of the chapter as a whole. It has indeed led us to a kind of All-unity, but one that is negative in character. It has made clear to us the limits of cognition, and if we try to step beyond them we will be moving within an enclosed circle. This circle is, admittedly, a large one. In a lecture-cycle (‘Human and Cosmic Thought’, GA 151) Rudolf Steiner describes it as consisting of twelve world-views which are determined by the forces of the various regions of the Zodiac (see Fig.168). (Through the influence of the planetary spheres each of these world-views assumes seven different nuances.) A study of the history of philosophy shows that, for the greater part, these world-views succumbed, in one form or another, to the prejudice that the world is our mental representation and the thing-in-itself of the percept is unknowable.

In order to escape from the blind alley of cognition, we must find our way from the periphery of the universe, from the circle of the twelve world-views – which in our time are all abstract – to its centre, but not in a naïve-realistic manner, not in order to begin to perceive the sense-world there individually, but to perceive there ideally. We have also been led by chapter 4 to make the following resolve: To accomplish the metamorphosis of consciousness, without which one cannot approach this centre with one’s individual ‘I’.

Let us now try to experience Cycle VII as a complete, concluding musical scale, which is compressed together into a single chord. Passing across it, we arrive at the ‘opposite bank’ in the structure of Part I of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’.

          CYCLE VII

1-2.          The way of thinking described above, which calls itself – in contrast to the standpoint of the naïve
          consciousness which it refers to as naïve realism – critical idealism, makes the mistake of characterizing
          the
one kind of percept as inner representation, while accepting the other kind in the manner of the naïve
          realism which it had apparently refuted. It wishes to prove that percepts are inner representations, while
          naïvely accepting percepts of our own organism as objectively valid facts, and, what is more, overlooking
          the fact that it confuses two spheres of observation, between which it can find no mediating element.
                 Critical idealism can only refute naïve realism by, itself, accepting in naïve realistic fashion the human
          organism as objectively existing. As soon as it becomes aware of the fact that the percepts of one’s own
          organism are of exactly the same kind as those which naïve realism assumes to have objective existence, it
          can no longer rest upon the former as a safe support. It would be obliged to regard its subjective organization,
          also, as a mere complex of inner representations. But this means it is no longer possible to think of the
          content of the perceived world as a product of our mental organization. One would have to accept the
          proposition that the inner representation ‘colour’ is merely a modification of the inner representation ‘eye’.
          The view known as critical idealism cannot be proved unless it borrows something from naïve realism.
          And the latter is only refuted if its own basic assumptions are left un- challenged in another sphere.

3.               From this we may conclude with certainty: investigation within the field of perception cannot prove
           the correctness of critical idealism and nor, therefore, can the percept be thus divested of its objective
           character.
                   Still less, however, can one regard the assertion
“The perceived world is my inner representation” as
           being self-evident and in no need of demonstration.

4.                Schopenhauer begins his principal work ‘The World as Will and Representation’ with the words: “The
           world is my inner representation (Vorstellung); – this is a truth that holds good with respect to every living
           and cognizing being, although the human being alone can bring it into reflective, abstract consciousness.
           If he really does this, philosophical self-knowledge has arisen in him. It then be- comes clear and certain
           to him that he has no knowledge of a sun or an Earth, but only of an eye which sees a sun, and of a hand
           which feels an Earth; that the world around him only exists as an inner representation – i.e. is only there
           with respect to another, the representing being, which is he himself. – If any truth can be uttered a priori,
           then it is this; as it is the statement of that form of all possible and conceivable experience which is more
           universal than any other – time, space and causality; as all these already presuppose it....”

5.                The entire proposition is refuted by the fact mentioned above, that eye and hand are no less percepts
           than sun and Earth.

6.                 And in the spirit of Schopenhauer one could respond to his words, echoing his own form of expression:
          “My eye, which sees the sun, and my hand, which feels the Earth, are my inner representations just as are
          the sun and the Earth themselves.” But that I thereby invalidate the original assertion, becomes immediately
          clear. For only my real eye and my real hand could have within them as their modifications the inner
          representations ‘sun’ and ‘Earth’; my inner representations ‘eye’ and ‘hand’ could not. But it is only of these
          that critical idealism is entitled to speak.

7.                  Critical idealism is quite unable to achieve insight into the relation between percept and inner
          representation. It cannot make the distinction we indicated earlier, between the nature of a percept during
          the act of perception and the attributes it must have before it is perceived. This will require us to follow
          another path.

* * *

Let us retrace our steps, as there are a number of issues that arose at an earlier stage, which we have not yet resolved. Let us look again at Cycle IV, but taking into account all that has been said since then. It begins with something that would appear, on the surface, to be extremely simple: an analysis of the first childhood perceptions, which many a naïve realist preserves unchanged, on into later life. The antithesis in this Cycle shows us that it is impossible to be simply given over to one’s perceptions. They come into contradiction with one another. And now there arises, out of quite simple and obvious observations, the judgment in the synthesis: the experience in the realm of perception comes into disagreement with the concepts. In addition, the line of reasoning contained in the synthesis finds support in the working of the law of the unity of soul-spiritual phylogenesis and ontogenesis: Every human being, beginning from birth, passes through the school of sense-perception, as the whole of humanity has done – “We see this in everyday life, just as in the spiritual development of mankind.”

After this, the conclusion we have reached is looked at in the sphere of experience of mankind in general. And here we are not dealing at all with child-like perceptions. We might even ask ourselves whether Goethe was really right when he said, “The senses do not deceive.”

In element 6 the soul-observations are brought in relation to the natural-scientific method. Then follows a general conclusion. If we now move on from Cycle IV in both directions, we find – with the help of physiology and psychology – in Cycle V a fundamental consideration of the consequences which are of the greatest importance for cognition and arise from the conclusion reached at the end of Cycle VII. “The senses do not deceive” is only true if one has a right spiritual attitude. If, however, one does not come through to a monistic view of the rela- tion of concept and percept, it is not at all right to place one’s trust in the experience of observation.

If we move backwards from Cycle IV, we also take, in Cycle III, a step towards the realm of concepts. With the experience of observations we proceed in the same way as in Cycle IV – we begin with what is immediately given to the senses. Then in Cycle II we focus on the thinking being and the forming of the relation between subject and object; and in Cycle I we move ‘outwards’: thinking “goes... beyond what is observed”. Looking at the opposite side, in Cycle VII we move in an ‘outward’ direction, where thinking assumes the form of critical idealism. One must not imagine that the evolutionary world-movement of thinking from centre to periphery arrives at the same result in each direction. All that works here universally is the principle of the relation of centre to periphery, to the circle, just as the germ-cell, for example, receives an instreaming of forces coming from the spiritual regions of the entire Zodiac, relative to which it represents the central point, alhough on different sides of it different organs unfold.

Now that we have reached the outer limits (beginning and end) of chapter 4, we will step beyond these limits and follow the first of the chains of thought-forms represented in Table 5. In chapter 1, as we recall, the basic question of the entire book is asked: – Can the human being be free in his thinking and his activity? The chapter ends with the conclusion that, in order to make a judgement regarding activity, one must first solve the question of the origin of thinking.

In Cycle I of chapter 4 we see that the concepts in our consciousness are ‘freed’ in a certain sense from our percepts. But they do not derive from the percepts; they merely unite with them. The concepts come from the sphere of thinking, which goes beyond what the human being observes.

In chapter 1 an investigation is made into the relations between cause and effect in the process of human activity, and it is pointed out that the mistake of many philosophers who deny freedom stems from their inability to distinguish between conscious and unconscious motives. This fact is confirmed with the help of a ‘beholding’ of the proofs offered by Spinoza, which are presented in chapter 1. Spinoza’s standpoint is mistaken, and in element 5 (of Cycle II) our task is, proceeding from the ‘beholding’ of a false observation, to recognize the truth of the matter.

We do approximately the same thing in Cycle I of chapter 4, only in our beholding we turn, not to Spinoza, but to Spencer (who had also been mentioned in chapter 1). And then, in element 5, proceeding from a beholding of a mistaken argument, we arrive at the conclusion that the concept of effect (or result) implies (Ger. – ‘draws after it’) the concept of cause. This conclusion thereby provides us with the solution to the question that was not understood by Spinoza. We can now say: The external reasons for our actions are percepts. However, these do not give rise in us to actions, but concepts; then, out of the concepts is born the decision. We have thus learnt something as to how a decision comes about. We were asked this question in chapter 1.

In Cycle 1 of chapter 4 we are confronted with an observation of Spencer’s which unfolds in a similar way to that of Spinoza, as described in the first chapter. Spinoza was of the opinion that the impulse enters us unconsciously and causes us to act. In a similar way, Spencer also wishes to convince us that the sound, and not the thought, prompts us to seek for the cause; here, too, it is not the conscious motive. Finally, it becomes clear to us that the thought inserts itself between the percept and the deed. The procession of metamorphoses which we have been studying moves on into Cycle VII of chapter 4. Here a comparison is made between the standpoints of the naïve and critical consciousness towards the problem of the relation between percept and concept. The discussion that has broken out again on this theme reminds us of the one in chapter 1. There is a correspondence between the naïve-realistic standpoint of Cycle VII and Spinoza’s position; and between Schopenhauer’s critical realism (Cycle VII) and the position of Hartmann (chapter 1). The naïve realist considers his own organism as an objectively significant fact (the actions of the child and the diplomat are “of one and the same kind”). The critical idealist, who has discovered in the end that he is a metaphysical realist, also adopts the standpoint of the naïve realist, with respect to the percept and to the motives of activity.

If we juxtapose chapter 1 with Cycle VII of chapter 4 we begin to understand how difficult it is to resolve the question of freedom in conditions where the sphere of percepts as motives is separated by an unbridgeable gulf from that of conscious motives. For the cognizing subject everything depends upon whether he is able to overcome the ‘two-worlds’ theory. This is the question that will concern us in our study of chapter 7, where the naïve realist and the metaphysical realist are again at odds in their attitude to monism and dualism. We thus see in how organic and cohesive a manner the metamorphosis of the thought-process takes its course on the first of three paths in the structure of the unitary metamorphosis of the entire first Part of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’. Adopting a still wider perspective, one can add that the question of freedom of action flows over into the question as to the possibility of the existence of the free individuality and, undergoing metamor- phosis in the second Part, finds its final resolution in chapter 14, which bears the heading ‘Individuality and Species’. There we are shown the ultimate liberation of the human being: his liberation from the human kingdom (from the fourth natural kingdom). We will fail to grasp the essential character of this final chapter if we do not acquire practice in the complicated metamorphoses of thought and meaning which arise within the unitary (and therefore monistic) structure of the book.

Without going into detail, we would remark that in the second chain of metamorphosis (see Table 5, on p.123 of this chapter) in chapter 2 we undertake a thorough analysis of the positions of the monists and dualists. This, as the beginning of a new cycle of metamorphoses, corresponds to the ascent of the first chain to the octave. We are led to the conclusion that we place ourselves over against the world when we reflect upon it. Therefore it is essential to investigate our own being, in order to find within it something greater than what is produced in it by this confrontation. And in Cycle II of chapter 4 it is proposed that we turn our attention from thinking to the thinking subject, which consciously observes the world as object and itself as subject. In Cycle VI of chapter 4 we have dealt thoroughly with the question, how this process takes place in the subject. In chapter 6 all the questions enumerated here come up again and are then considered in the light of the human individuality.

In the third chain of metamorphosis, we investigated in chapter 3 how, in the subject, in the human individuality, observation and thinking stand in relation to one another: these two being the ‘starting- points’ for any conscious deed. Thus, in the third chain the questions that have been considered separately in the first two chains – concerning the percept and then the concept – are drawn together to a single question. Here, thinking is regarded as a special kind of activity which can be perceived and also thought. Thus monism receives its principal support. In Cycle III of chapter 4 we investigate the way in which the object of observation comes to meet thinking, the self-conscious subject. The question is, admittedly, not entirely resolved here. But it is asked, and we register the fact that the way the thought-content appears to consciousness is also as a percept. This question is taken up in Cycle V of chapter 4. That which is lasting and enduring (consciousness, the ‘I’) is here separated out from what is transitory (the percept). Once again, the standpoint of Spinoza comes to the fore, but now within the sphere of the activity of cognition. “I do not merely see a tree; I also know that it is I who am seeing it.” And, finally, in chapter 5 all that has been considered previously, rises a stage higher. The positions of the naïve realist, the transcendentalist, solipsist, the physiologist who researches into sense-perception, collapse, because they are unable to prove that the world is my inner representation. The cognizing human being is that indispensable link, thanks to which cognition draws together to a unity the world that has been split into two by the subject himself.

We have thus discovered, in our movement along the three lemnis- cates, the consistent development of the content, not only to the left of chapter 4 in the direct sequence of the text, but also to the right of it, in the reverse sequence: from chapters 7 to 4. In one of his lectures of 1923, towards the end of his life, Rudolf Steiner said of this puzzling and mysterious book: “No-one who lacks independence in his thinking can understand this book. Right from the beginning and page by page the reader must acquire the habit of returning to his etheric body, in order to be able to have the kind of thoughts that are contained in this book. For this reason, the book is a path of training” (GA 350, 28.6.1923).

The analysis of structure and content of Part I of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’, which we are carrying out here, has to do with nothing other than ‘etheric thinking’, in which it is possible to move, not in a straight line, but only on a lemniscate, from the periphery to the centre, ascending on the stages of development from the less perfect to the more perfect, etc. Here one must learn to think in inversions, within the element of will, because in the ether body the laws of thinking are the laws of life. In the place of formal logic there comes something that could be tentatively called logical organology. Let us now conclude with an analysis of the structure of the chapter as set forth by us, with its component parts placed in juxtaposition to one another.


Element 1

thesis

Element 3

synthesis

Element 5

ideal perception

Element 7

All-unity

C. I

Through think- ing, concepts and ideas arise. The concept is that which corresponds to the object on an ideal level

The concept is not obtained through observation. Concepts combine together into a system

The percept gives rise to the concept of result or effect, and this prompts us to seek for the concept of the cause of the percept

Thinking takes us beyond what is observed

C. II

Human consciousness is the place where concepts and percepts meet and combine together

Consciousness is the mediator between thinking and observation

Human conscious- ness is self- consciousness. When we reflect upon thinking, we have our own subject as an object

Thinking leads the human being beyond himself, unites him with the objects and places him over against them as an individual

C. III

How does the object of observation enter our consciousness?

Thinking finds conceptual connections between the observations and brings them thereby into a mutual relationship

The relations established by thinking between the observations are objective

Through observation we come to experience thinking. This is also a percept

162

C. IV

The naïve human being believes that percepts are not dependent on him, and are in the precise form in which he receives them

Every extension of the circle of percepts alters my picture of the world

What is it that causes us to correct our observations?

My percept-images appear to me in the first place to be subjective

C. V

If percepts are subjective, does anything of an objective character underlie them?

What is the role of the subject in the process of perception?

It is brought about by our inner representations, which are given to us in the percept of our ‘I’. This remains constant in the fluctuation of our percepts

In my percepts I have two worlds: an outer and an inner (the world of my self-perception)

C. VI

In philosophy it is falsely asserted that we only perceive our inner representations

The assertion that we only have inner representations and cannot have knowledge of percepts is a result of mistaken thinking

Denial by the physiologists of the objectivity of perception is a grave mistake in the analysis of observations

But how the two worlds join together is still unclear. What is perceived, and how?

C. VII

Such is critical idealism. It naïvely regards the human being’s perception of the organism as objective, i.e. it behaves in the same way as the naïve realist

Critical idealism is unable to prove the subjective nature of percepts. And it is not axiomatic that the world is my inner representation

But such, too, are the argument of many philosophers who conclude that the world is my inner representation

What happens to the percept during the act of perception, and what must be in it prior to this? A way must be found, that will enable us to resolve this question

Table 6

An analysis of the vertical columns of this Table shows conclusively that we have here to do with seven-membered thought-cycles. Our final résumé:

Through thinking, concepts and ideas arise. Thinking leads the subject beyond himself and unites him with the objects, but also sets them over against him. It forms objective relations between the observations, and can itself become an object of observation. What happens to the percept during the act of perception, when it is in the one case sense-object and in the other case an object of thought?


The Three Aspects of Symmetry

Sevenfoldness is organized by way of threefoldness. One of the forms in which this comes to expression is the principle of symmetry in the seven-membered metamorphoses. It is the source of reciprocal transformations within holistic objects. The principle of symmetry is contained within dialectical triads. It results in a polar inversion of the mirrored antitheses of being and non-being, whereupon becoming arises. This can convince us of the fact that the principle of symmetry is dynamic. The spiritual-scientific doctrine of becoming speaks of at least three principles of symmetry. They are all united and revealed within a sevenfold metamorphotic lemniscate, regardless of its content. The first principle of symmetry is expressed in the axis or surface (a lemniscate can be three-dimensional) separating one loop of the lemniscate from the other. This axis or surface finds its ‘ur’-phenomenal principle in the universal plan of the world, in accordance with which the Divine primordial revelation is reflected in the ‘otherness-of-being’ of evolution. The latter is the mirror-reflection of the Tri-unity. They are separated by the symmetry-plane (or line, or it may be no more than a point) which has become the boundary between two worlds – the supersensible and the sense-worlds. The nature of this plane or surface is the state of consciousness (Fig.62).

Thus, the principle of symmetry in the evolution of the world is the process of becoming, the becoming of consciousness – i.e. of the ‘I’ in its direct or indirect expression. The geometric picture of the world shown in Fig.62 is projected onto the thinking spirit of the human being and is realized in his process of becoming as it moves from the abstract to the beholding consciousness. The Tri-unity of the primordial revelation becomes, in its mirror-reflection, the dialectical tri-unity, in which it finds its complete non-being. Through the ‘I’s becoming, higher and universal being is brought in dynamic relation to non-being, and then the dialectical triad receives its living counterpart in the triad of beholding.

The first principle of symmetry we have found does not reveal to us immediately the character of its working. It is the source of various kinds of dualism and remains for conceptual ‘I’-consciousness the ‘thing-in-itself’. Dualism is overcome with the help of the second principle of symmetry. As axis (or plane) this runs in vertical relation to the axis of the first principle. Its expression in esotericism is the magical staff of Mercury. Thanks to this principle the metamorphoses within the cycle are held in a unity. In the evolution of the world it runs as a unitary axis (the line of the chalice-form) through all seven aeons. (Here, the first principle corre- sponds to the axis of world-symmetry).The earthly aeon represents, in this case, the crossing-point of the two principles of symmetry, and it is therefore precisely here that the human being develops his individual ‘I’ (Fig.63).

* Seen from another viewpoint, one can regard the first principle of sym- metry as the axis of evolution, and the second as the axis of ascending and descending ‘I’-consciousness, and also as the axis of world-symmetry.
______

The ‘I’ has the character of a ‘point’, in the sense that it calls forth only qualitative metamorphosis: by it the external is made internal, it sets involution over against evolution, and vice-versa, etc. Thus the ‘I’ constitutes the third principle of symmetry, and at the same time the unity of all three. It is, itself, non-spatial; or, rather, it belongs to the zero-dimension (the point-like space) of the world of intuition. But when it is active as the principle of becoming, it leads the two-dimensionality of the other two principles into a unity with itself, and then development enters the three-dimensionality of the material world, and the space-time continuum comes into being. In the lemniscates of the seven-membered cycles of thinking, in which the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ is written, we remain from the beginning within two-dimensional space; the third principle of symmetry has a point-like character. It is the point of the transformation of the lower ‘I’ into the higher, which can only occur as a qualitative ‘leap’ (Fig.64); but this is prepared through work done in the flow of time.

The first principle of symmetry separates the understanding-nature from the beholding-nature and indicates for us that their relation is one of mirror-reflection, so to speak. The second principle of symmetry combines within it the 2nd, 4th and 6th elements of the seven-membered thought-cycle; those elements, therefore, in which the complex of forces at work as between lower ‘I’ and higher ‘I’ must be particularly active. This axis organizes the symmetry of content present in elements 1 and 3, and also 5 and 7; and in addition their transverse symmetry 1-7 and 3-5.

If he wishes to be able realize ‘beholding’ thinking, the human being needs to enter with his lower ‘I’ into point 4 and try to undertake all that is neces- sary for the metamorphoses of the thought-cycle, appealing as he does so to the power of the higher ‘I’. Within the configuration of the whole of Part 1 of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’, it is chapter 4 which corresponds to this point. Here the ‘becoming’ of the ‘I’ begins. As a principle of symmetry, this is the mid-point of the circle, whose periphery dissolves into spiritual heights. On the conceptual level, it is the centre of the Zodiac of the twelve world-views (Fig.168, p.25). In the structure and the text of the ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ is contained the working of the higher ‘I’. Merely to grasp its structure reunites our lower ‘I’ with the higher ‘I’. Let us try, therefore, to experience the content of the first Part of the book in its symmetry, as represented in Fig.65.

Thus is realized the Tri-unity in the seven-membered metamorphosis of development. When a movement of the metamorphoses takes place in this way, the content of the chapters become initially ever more complex; this reaches its climax in chapter 4 and then, in essence, becomes gradually simpler. Actually, it grows simpler on both sides of the first principle of symmetry, if we follow its axis downwards. As far as the cognizing ‘I’ is concerned, the beginning of its activity is found at the centre of chapter 4. The content, structure and dynamics of the thinking, its intentionality – all this remains, thanks to the three principles of symmetry, within a unity, and can be recognized in its relation to different axes of symmetry. This is yet another aspect (a subordinate part) of the logic of beholding in thinking.





Chapter 5
Contents
Chapter 7



<font face="Helvetica, Arial, sans-serif">G. A. Bondarev - Rudolf Steiner’s ‘Philosophie der Freiheit’ As the Foundation of the Logic of Beholding Thinking. Religion of the Thinking Will. Organon of the New Cultural Epoch. Volume 2</font>